LAW AND THE STATE
Harold J. Laski
Studies in Law and
Politics
Yale University Press, 1932
chapt. XI, p. 237
[**197] Every state in the
modern world is a territorial community in the
name of which some agent or agents exercise sovereignty. By
sovereignty is
meant the legal competence to issue orders without
a need to refer to a higher authority. The orders so issued
constitute law, and are binding upon all who come within
their
jurisdiction.
In some such way as
this the modem analytical jurist defines die
nature of the state for the
purposes of his science. Any explanation
of its character is, most usefully, of two kinds. It can be, on the
one
hand, historical. It is possible to trace the way in which the
Respublica Christiana [Christian Commonwealth]
of the Middle
Ages was slowly transformed into the complex of states we know in
the modem world, and to show how the demands of unity and
order gradually and painfully resulted in the attribution to them of
the quality we call sovereignty. Such
an explanation has the value
of enabling us to see that the modem state is not, either in its form
or substance, anything permanent or eternal: it is simply a
moment of historical time, obviously born of special needs, and,
equally obviously, destined to
transformation either when it has
ceased to satisfy those needs or when the needs themselves have
passed away. The historical study of the state has the great merit
of
showing us the essentially pragmatic character of all theories about
its nature. They are
born of the need to satisfy a particular
environment, and they die when they cease to render that
satisfaction.
Alternatively, the
jurists explanation of the state may dwell in [**198] the realm of formal logic. Making
entire abstraction of the facts of
any given state, it may seek the
quintessential form of which all
states are more or less imperfect expressions. It may then say that
where there is an authority which fixes the norms of all law, and
beyond which, in the search for the origin of such norms,
we
cannot go, there we have a sovereign state. The content of
the
norms, or of the orders begotten legally of them, is here
irrelevant.
Neither political nor moral considerations have any bearing upon
this aspect of statehood. We have not to consider
the goodness or
badness, the wisdom or unwisdom, of the norms; no problem
arises for the jurist save whether the authority which has fixed
them is or is not competent formally to do so, whether it is possible
to go beyond that authority to one upon which
it depends for its
existence. If there is formal competence, if, further, that authority
is ultimate in what may be termed the hierarchy of powers, it
constitutes a sovereign state.
From a
formal point of view, it is clear that the juristic theory of
the state explains why
commands which are issued in the name of
the state are binding upon all who come within its jurisdiction. For
it makes the ultimate source of reference from which all legal
power to command is derived. But it is important to remember
what
the theory does not do. It explains how a complex of
personalities, both corporate and individual, is geared into unity
by subordinating them to a single point in the community. It does
not explain whether the method by which this result is attained is
good or whether its
consequences are beneficial. It defines law as
he will of the state without regard to the content of law. It makes
that will binding upon the subjects of the state without regard
either to what it does or to its power to get itself applied.
It does
not explain why the state has acted in a particular way, or
whether
it should have acted in a particular way. It is merely a
descriptive
technique of competence, independent of the actual world that
competence will have to encounter. It is entirely
fair, from this
angle, to speak of the will of the state as absolute, indivisible,
and
inalienable. For were it none of these things, it would, in terms of
its definitions, cease to be sovereign. Any formal juristic theory of
the state conceived in
this way must necessarily dwell in a pure
world of categories. It is independent of the day-to-day stresses
and
strains which states have to encounter. The ideal state of
formal
jurisprudence need not consider public opinion, the wills of other [**199]
states, the impact upon itself of internal and competing powers,
ethical right, or political wisdom. Within the structure of the
community of which it is the supreme expression, life is lived in
terms of categories which it alone can make or alter. It determines
the life of all
other wills because it alone makes the principles of
behaviour to which they must conform. For their law is conceived
in terms of its law, since rules of conduct hostile to its law are
illegal
in the precise degree in which they depart from it. We are, indeed,
entitled to think of them as valid only by reason of state
permission, since the possibility that the state may deny them
renders their right to be an exercise always in the conditional
mood. The state giveth, and the state taketh
away; whether we shall
add the wonted blessing depends very largely upon our
political
philosophy.
II
In
terms of its axioms, formal jurisprudence is completely justified in the whole
of its procedure; in terms of its axioms, neither its method nor its results
can be denied. By its own inherent logic, all
that it makes law is necessarily legal, all in conflict with it
is
necessarily illegal; for it could not continue its sovereignty on
any
other terms. But a philosophy of the state can never rest satisfied
with the axioms
of formal jurisprudence. It must ask why they have
been assumed, and what they do as a consequence of their
adoption. It must seek a bridge between the purely logical world of
ideal concepts, in which alone the juristic theory of the state
dwells, and the
actual world about us, in which the states that we
know have to perform their function. It needs to know,
accordingly,
what that function is, and, independently of the
juristic theory, to devise an institutional pattern which seems
most
likely to enable it to be performed to the maximum
possible
advantage. When the juristic theory is analysed from this angle,
its
nature and validity begin to assume a much more questionable
form.
Let us
begin by remembering two things. Every state, from the
legal angle, is divisible
into a body of persons issuing orders, and a
body of persons receiving them and, presumably, acting upon
them. The latter encounter the state always through its agents. It
cannot act upon them except through its agents. For them, the
[**200] state itself is an abstraction in the name of which
those agents are
entitled to speak. They make its will for the subjects of the state,
in
whom, of course, where the state is a Rechtsstaat, they are
themselves included. Save through them, the state
has no means
of declaring its will. It is simply a category of description, a method
of attributing formal competence of a specially majestic kind to
certain persons and not to other persons. There is nothing about
the state, in this context, which
enables us to assume that it has
special virtues or special wisdom, or an inherent right (apart from
a formal legal right) to be obeyed. Its sovereignty is a method
of
conferring formal power upon men to whom functions of a special
kind have been entrusted.
The way
in which this kind of power developed is well known.
When the western world split up, at the Reformation, into a series
of communities no longer recognizing either a single religious
head, as in the Pope, or a vague and tenuous overlordship, as in
the Emperor, religious
conflict made necessary the unification of
power within the state if it was to survive the consequences of
that
conflict. Sometimes the solution took the form of assuming that
the decisions for making unity, and, therefore, order, should
rest
with the prince who became, as with Henry VIII and Elizabeth
I,
the supreme head of the church; sometimes the unity was made
by
recognizing papal power as invested with a right to command
Roman Catholics, but, also, investing another authority with
the
right to determine, as in France under the Bourbons, the
limits
within which that power should be exercised. The Reformation, in
fact, transferred to a person, whether individual or institutional,
in
each of the communities into which Europe was broken up the
power to
determine the rights of groups and persons in the
interests of peace and order. Continuous warfare made men feel
that peace was the supreme good; uncertainty whether the claim
of a group or person was valid or not seemed to involve the risk
of
further conflict. To set the monarch, or, as in England, the King
in
Parliament, above all other persons in the community was a simple
way of resolving what rights those persons should possess. None of
them, legally, could appeal to a will beyond that
of the King, or his
analogue. They had, therefore, in the legal realm no alternative
but obedience to his decision. The supremacy of the state was,
internally, the necessary consequence of the breakdown of
religious unity. Its right to determine the
boundaries of power in [**201] any association or
person within the community over which it
presided followed directly from that supremacy. Once there was
no appeal to Rome, there was no power which could compete with
the authority of the state. But it must be remembered,
once more,
that in all these relationships, the state acted always through
agents: it was, for its subjects, Philip in Spain, Louis in
France,
Cromwell and his major-generals, or William and his Parliaments
in England. Their right to issue
orders was the expression of a
relational context between them and other persons so placed as to
be unable, by legal means, to go beyond them. What is termed
the
personality of the state was, in point of fact, always the personality
of the government of
the state. The distinction between state and
government was nothing more than the means of obtaining a
sanction for the norms imposed by the government upon the
community.
The
international situation greatly helped this development.
The growth of commerce meant that, internally,
the interests of
peace were paramount; and the government of the state, as the
authority charged with the preservation of order, enormously
increased its authority as a consequence. Once commerce passed,
in fact, from the local to the
national sphere, the government was
able, in the name of the state, to make regulations which, in the
interest of the whole community, could be regarded as
superseding merely local advantage. And where war was deemed
necessary for commercial advantage,
obviously it was to the
economic benefit of the interests affected to strengthen the
authority of the state, therefore, also, of government, for their
own
sake. By the middle of the seventeenth century, government and
state had become so identified that even
dynastic wars contributed
to the interest of the states authority. Its power grew by leaps
and
bounds simply because the purposes it represented were attained
by its increasing assumption of authority.
That
this is the history of its development is brought out clearly
by the history of political philosophy since the Reformation.
The
classical theory of the state, as it passes from Luther to Bodin,
thence to Hobbes and Rousseau, and ultimately to Hegel and his
disciples, is essentially the history of
an axiom and its justification.
Luther vindicated the right of the secular power to be,
independently of ecclesiastical trammels. Bodin and Hobbes,
writing, each of them, in an age when the power of the [**202] government to speak in the name of the
state was challenged,
insisted that anything less than a sovereign state meant anarchy,
because there was then no final source of certain reference for the
norms by which mens behaviour is regulated. Both Bodin
and
Hobbes wrote in an age when the monarchical principle seemed
to most thinkers by all odds the most satisfactory. It was a
principle
Rousseau could not accept. But the real upshot of his work was, by
making the state the repository of the general will, to give to its
agents a moral sanction they
could hardly have otherwise claimed.
For his denial that representative government is valid was omitted
from the synthesis built in his name; and once it could be stated
that the people could act only through its elected representatives,
a penumbra of prestige
was added to their activity which could in
no other manner have been obtained. The inference, in fact, was
drawn by Hegel who made the state, and, inferentially, the agents
who act in its name, not only the culmination of the social process,
but the
embodiment of the highest purpose humanity could know.
Thenceforward, to challenge the state was not merely to challenge
the source of peace and order, but to challenge, also, that in which
the highest end of man was incarnate; and since the state could be
challenged effectively
only by a challenge to its government- since
the latter only disposed of the states sovereignty the
moral
beatification of government seemed to follow from the function
it
performed as the supreme agent of the state purpose.
III
The problem
of the juristic philosopher, in short, is the difficult
one of validating his purely formal analysis of categories for the
actual world about us. Institutions justify themselves, not by
their
position in a logical hierarchy, and the claims that position
formally entities them to make, but by their power to satisfy
effective demand. Once they fail in this, new institutions
become
necessary, and a new hierarchy is developed to make the logical
hierarchy more adequate to our needs. And
this, in fact, is what is
happening today. Social changes, on the one hand, and
scientific
development, on the other, have operated to revolutionize the
position of government both in the national state and in the
international community. An adequate legal
philosophy, that is to
say, must not only explain the legal right of a government to [**203]
obedience, but its ethical right as well. It must not only do this.
It
must explain, also, how the sovereignty of the state can be
reconciled with a world in which the hinterland
between states is
organized, must show, therefore, how a state which is the subject
of a vast range of determinate obligations can remain subject to no
will save its own, and yet remain under compulsion to fulfil
its
obligations. Increasingly, the inadequacy of the classical theory
of
the state to express the needs of our time is evident to the
new
generation. Duguit in France, Kelsen in Vienna, Krabbe in
Holland are only the most eminent of those who, in various ways,
have admitted its bankruptcy
by seeking to built it anew on
different foundations. None of the new answers maybe adequate;
but all of them represent a recognition that a purely formal jurisprudence
which seeks to explain the state as justified to its
members simply as the highest
unity-making factor we know is
without meaning for the problems of our time.
This
can, I think, be demonstrated by an examination of the
axioms on which formal jurisprudence has been constructed.
Those axioms arose out of a supreme need for order which had to be established
in a way which satisfied a set of given social
conditions. The supremacy of the state was achieved because it
enabled those who actually held power, those, also, whose tenure
of power was accepted, to exert authority in a formal way. Their
exercise of
authority satisfied their subjects at any rate to the degree that, broadly
speaking, was necessary to secure obedience.
But power can only be retained upon the saving condition that its
exercise continues to satisfy its subjects. Men who are conscious
of
wants ask themselves whether attention is paid to their wants. They scrutinize
the forms of the state in order to see whether those
forms are such as to offer them the maximum possible certainty
that their wants will be satisfied by them. And,
in the long run, the
forms are judged by the opinion built out of their actual operation.
Law
apart, every community is a congeries of men and
associations seeking the satisfaction of wants. Not all of them
are
attainable; some, at least, are incompatible with each other.
Some,
by their nature, demand the imposition of uniform rules of
behaviour either upon all members of the community or upon all
members who fall within a particular category. The desire, for
instance, for security of the person means
the imposition upon all
members of the community of the rule that murder is forbidden [**204]
and will be punished. A group within the community is charged
with the application of that rule. Men generally obey the orders
issued for the prevention of murder because they are
satisfied by
the consequences of that prevention. It is clear that if the
group
entrusted with the application of the rule were unable to secure
its
observance, other men would be entrusted with the task so long a
men continued to regard
security of the person as a desirable
object of attainment.
It is
in these terms that we must approach the position of the
state in society. It is entrusted with power in order that it may
satisfy, or organize the satisfaction of, the wants of men on the
largest possible
scale. It acts through a body of agents, the
government, to that end and no other end. It does not possess
power for the sake of power; it does not even possess power for the
order which power enables it to enforce, since order is not the
highest good, but
merely a means to the attainment of goods
regarded as higher than itself. For, clearly, a savage despot
might
establish a rˇgime in which order prevailed, but from which
freedom and justice and honourable dealings between men were
all absent.
Order, in that event, would be akin to the annihilation
of personality and could hardly be regarded as an end. Power,
there- fore, is not good in itself; a government which exercises
power is not, either, good in itself. Its goodness, or badness, is a
function of what
it does. Its nature is dependent upon the results
it secures by its operations.
Results
for whom? I see no answer to this question capable, at
least, of ethical justification, except the answer that it must be
results for every member of the community. For
the community is
a body of individuals, and goodness for the community must mean
goodness for those individuals or it means nothing; since, if
those
individuals are abstracted, no community is left And since the
humanity of men is dependent
upon their recognition as ends in
themselves, goodness for the community must mean goodness for
me as well as for another; for, otherwise, I cease to be an end in
myself and become merely a means to the ends of others, which,
being the definition of slavery,
is a denial of my humanity and a
refusal to recognize my status as a member of the community. The
state, therefore, as it operates, must treat my claim to good as equal
to that of another unless it shows that differentiation in its
treatment of me
involves some good in which my good is involved. [**205]
The
norms of law, therefore, that are established by the state -
that is, established or maintained by the government which is
exercising sovereignty in its name are norms the substance
of
which is of the first importance for the validation of its claim to
my
obedience. For its demand that I should obey any given norm
clearly depends, at least in part, on my recognition that my good
is
involved in that obedience. Mostly, without doubt, I shall obey
its
demand whatever its substance, since the comparison between
its
power and my own leaves me little alternative. But the norms
it
establishes may arouse dissent not only in me but also, it may be,
in a considerable number of persons like-minded with myself.
I
may dissent, for instance, as a member of the Roman Catholic
Church in the Kulturkampf; or I may dissent as a member of the
South Wales Miners Federation in the munitions strike of 1915;
or
I may dissent as a citizen who, in Russia during 1917, accepts the
principles of Revolutionary Communism. In these cases the formal
capacity of government to make law is challenged by a refusal to
accept the law it seeks to make. In crucial instances, that
formal
capacity remains purely formal; an attempt by the government
to
validate it in the event is met by a resistance which changes
the
government of the state. The unity of the state, of, that is, the
legal
system summarized in its power, may remain; but it remains on
the
condition that it is used for different purposes.
From
this I draw two inferences. In the first place I infer that the
validation of law is not a matter of the source from which it
emanates, but of the acceptance which it secures; and, in the
second place, I infer that it is the part of wisdom
so to organize the
ultimate law-making body of the state that is, the government
-
that a maximum consent to its operations is assured before it
embarks upon them. Consent to law is not merely a function of the
source of law. It is doubtless
true that innumerable men obey the
state simply because the government which issues an order is
entitled in law to speak in its name. But analysis would, I think,
show that most of such obedience is the product of habit or inertia,
and that it is never
creative. The obedience that counts is the
obedience of an actively consenting mind; and such a mind is
concerned less with the source of law than with what the law
proposes to do. This is always evident when the will of government
is opposed by some powerful
will which dissents from its
conclusions. Governments, at the margin, are rarely able to get [**206] their way if a considerable body of persons announce their refusal
to accept their proposals. They can then only exercise their
sovereignty at the risk of losing it. The
fact is that no government
represents the whole community in a way that ensures automatic
acceptance of its will. What it represents is an outlook which,
because it temporarily possesses effective power, is legally entitled
to use the machinery
of the state for purposes it deems good. If
that outlook conflicts with the outlook of other members of the
community, an attempt at its application may meet an attitude
which varies from secret evasion, thought passive resistance, to
active rebellion.
Law is made effective, that is to say, through the
fact of consent in those to whom it applies. There are limits to
effective legal action. This is another way of saying that the unity
the state is legally entitled to make, it cannot practically make
except upon conditions.
There is thus a serious disparity between
the requirements of formal law and the necessities which actual
law encounters.
It is
easy to see why this is the case. Every community has groups
of citizens to whom certain things are fundamental. They will
fight
for the preservation of those things, and any attempt to invade
them by the sovereign power will result in a challenge to the
sovereign power. There are English men, I think, who would resist
an attempt to abolish the enfranchisement
of the working class, or
the right to industrial combination, or the re-establishment
of
limitations upon freedom of religious belief. Legally, the King
in
Parliament could do any of these things; politically, by doing so,
it
would probably cease to be the King in Parliament. Legally, I
think, the King in Parliament has the formal right to resume an
active control of the affairs of the Dominions; politically it must, as
in the Declaration of 1926, treat them as equal and independent
states individually
entitled to make up their own minds about their
own problems, capable, of course, of being especially influenced
by the opinion of the British government, but never subject to its
legal control. Citizens, in a word, expect from government
certain
standards of conduct; and it lives by its ability to satisfy
those
standards. Its legal capacity is always set in the perspective of
the
limitations those standards impose. They determine its will since,
when they are set at nought, it ceases to have a will because it
15
driven to dissolution by refusal of allegiance.
Formal
law makes this allegiance single; the facts make it [**207]
multiple. Allegiance goes, not with the legal claim of the state, but
with the conduct of the organization which demands it. A man may
be with his church
and against the state, with his trade union, or
his party, if the facts seem to him to warrant that answer to the call.
He does not recognize an a
priori hierarchy of claims, which receive
their ultimate expression in the state. Law as form is psychologically
neutral to him; what gives it the validity of right is
its content upon a particular occasion where conflict has arisen.
He does
not assume in actual life that the state is entitled to his
loyalty because, as the state, it is acting in his interest.
He examines
what is done in its name and makes a judgement upon the moral quality of the
order he is asked to obey. He knows, that is, that legal
power, as such, is at every instant subject to perversion. No government is,
for him, entitled to permanent credit merely
because it is a government. It is liable to error, to perversion,
to
deliberate misuse of power. It may, consciously or unconsciously,
identify the interest of a class or a group or a party with the interest of
the community, and legislate upon the basis of that supposed
identity. It may do this in good faith; it may do this, also, in
bad
faith. No government can be known from the simple fact that it is
a government It can be known only from the character of its acts.
Nothing is
more clear historically than the fact that men judge
that character as the acts impinge upon them, as they respond or
fail to respond, to the expectations they have formed. Allegiance as a
psychological and historic fact is always contingent. It becomes
actual and effective
in terms of the quality of law rather than of its
source.
It is
because of this that men have sought in every age
institutional means of limiting the power of their governors. They have wished
to define what law shall be used for, to what purposes
alone its coercive
authority shall be devoted. Constitutions, Bills of
Rights, and the rest, are, after all, nothing more than ways of declaring that
the ends of law make law valid, and not the mere
source from which it emanates. It is because of this,
also, that every
age has seen a revival of the idea of natural law. That revival is nothing so
much as an effort on the part of thinkers to recall the
state to the purposes by which alone the exercise of authority can
be justified. It is an announcement
that positive law must run in the leading-strings of principle, that it is the
thing it is seeking to
establish which makes it binding upon those whose behaviour it is
[**208] to
control. Men struggle, in fact, against being imprisoned in the
categories of formal law
because they realize that unfettered
authority as such cannot give rise to an obligation which, a
priori,
is entitled to claim allegiance. The very ideal of a Rechtsstaat is
an
effort to make the legal sovereign the subject of purposes outside
itself. It
is a denial that it can will what it pleases. It is an insistence
that it is justified in willing only what satisfies the demands of
those
over whom it rules.
IV
At this
point, those who defend the classic theory of sovereignty,
even in one or other of
its contemporary attenuated forms, fall
back upon a new line of defence.[1]
They admit that the supreme
power of the state is merely a description of capacity within the
realm of formal law. They agree that such a view of sovereignty as
formal law demands is
politically inadequate and sociologically
unsatisfactory. But they argue that its retention as a concept
is
necessary because society needs an organ formally entitled to
resolve conflict between individuals and groups within itself.
Unless
there is to be anarchy in society, they say, there must be a
highest power somewhere to which reference can be made where
disagreement arises. A political system, said Madison in
the
Philadelphia Convention,[2]
which does not contain an effective provision for the peaceable
solution of all controversies arising
within itself, would be a Government in name only. There
must,
therefore, be some body within the community which, when
controversy comes, can say the last word. Or there may
even be
more than one body, each of which, as in a federal system, is
final
in the particular sphere in which it presides. Only so can we
safeguard ourselves against the danger of particularism.
I am
unable to see that the argument is a valid one, and I do not
believe that
is exponents have adequately examined the presuppositions upon which it rests.
In so far as it is an insistence that the
state must necessarily perform the chief part in co-ordinating
social activities, and that it cannot accept dictation from
any other
authority in performing that function, it merely repeats the
argument of formal jurisprudence; and, as I have here sought to
show, so long as it remains within that sphere, it is impossible to [**209]
controvert the position it assumes from the very nature of
the
axioms upon which it is founded.
But its
exponents go further than this: they claim that its
solutions have a validity other than purely formal because,
somehow, the state is a safeguard against particularistic interests.
It is acting in the name of
the whole community. It makes peace
possible. It is free from the partial views which permeate
inevitably the attitude of groups and individuals lesser than
itself.
The whole of this argument seems to me fallacious in so far as
it
seeks to make these qualities necessary and a priori
attributes of the
state. It omits certain relevant facts of the highest importance from
the view it seeks to establish. It forgets, first, that the state of
which
it speaks is an abstraction; that what we have to examine are
the
acts of the government which speaks in its name. We cannot a priori say that the decision of this government, in any given instance, is
in the interest of the whole community until we know what the
content of the decision is. That judgement,
obviously, must be
pronounced by those who are to be affected by it. To say that they must accept
it because its rejection imperils peace is to argue that
order is, and always must be, the highest good. I do not see that it
is possible to
take this view on any scrutiny of historical facts. I do
not find it possible to blame, for example, those who resisted
Charles I in 1642, or the men who revolted in France in 1789, or
in Russia in March of 1917. No government acts in the name of the
community
save in a formal sense until the opinion of the
community upon its action is known. Governments have exercised
the sovereign power for particularistic ends in the past, and they
will, doubtless, do so again in the future. When Louis XIV revoked
the
Edict of Nantes his action was dictated by the view that the interest of
France
demanded a single pattern of religious outlook; his action, we
need not doubt, was both sincere and built upon high motives. But
I do not see why the Huguenots were not, equally
sincerely and
from high motives, entitled to resist his decision. The order he
sought to establish was, for them, the abrogation of all they held most dear;
and their judgement, as with [the Calvinist theologian]
Jurieu, that this was a case where acquiescence
in the will of the state
merely because it was the will of the state was impossible, seems to
me a justified one.
I
entirely agree with the view that the cases where men or [**210]
associations oppose the will of the state should always be cases
of
last instance; I do not need to be convinced that peace is
almost
always better than conflict But it is not so always. Because it is not
so always legal claims are merely legal, and, as such, have no
necessary connection with justice. Every sovereign act of
the state
is always, equally with the judgement of every other element
in
society, someones act, whether of individual or group. It may
be
made with good will; it may be made with bad will. It has no
inherent virtue as a sovereign act It draws its
quality from its consequences. Both morally and politically, it is neutral save
in the
context of those consequences. Any theory of sovereignty which
would make it more than this suffers from the fallacy which
identifies a maintenance of the power of the state
with the
preservation of general social well-being. There is no way
of
knowing whether that correspondence is justified until we know what the state
actually does.
Now the
state, as I have pointed out, exists to satisfy the largest
possible volume of demand in the community.
It co-ordinates the
bewildering mass of activities there to secure the greatest measure
of common satisfaction. That is the justification of its legal
authority, the sole ground upon which coercive powers are
entrusted to it, and
to no other group of persons within the community. The question of whether it
fulfils its function
adequately is obviously incapable of an a priori
answer. Some of
those who have sought to give the juristic theory of sovereignty a
place beyond its formal sphere have seen this.
They have therefore
,wished to transfer the argument to the way in which the sovereign
power is organized. Obviously, if it is to fulfil its task adequately, it must
be organized to that end. Let us so organize it, and it can
then claim an
authority to which, otherwise, it could not pretend.
The
argument is an important one, and it must be developed in
some little detail if we are properly to appreciate its
significance.
Every community is so complex in its nature that, except for the
formal purposes of
law, it cannot be reduced to the unity of a
single common good. There are interests in it which are
permanently antithetic, those, for instance, of a Roman Catholic
to whom the propositions of the Syllabus of 1864 are ultimate
truth, and
those of a Martian Communist who discovers ultimate
truth in the pronouncements of the Third International. 1f there is never a
unity of common good, no organ in the society can do [**211] more
than partially express the common goods upon which men
agree. We make unities;
we can never make unity itself. What we
attain, at best, is never total satisfaction of demands, but
partial
satisfaction, sufficient, at best, to preserve a working compromise
which men accept as less inadequate than any other to which they
can lay their
hand. Now the state which has power to co-ordinate
the demands that are made needs, if it is to be successful, the
fullest possible knowledge of those demands. It must not, so to
say,
either ignore them or legislate for them. It must legislate
through
them. The organ which exercises its sovereignty must be so
constituted as to represent not some part, or aspect, of the demands to
be satisfied, but the largest possible area of those demands.
Society, if I may so phrase it, is federal in its nature;
and the
authority, accordingly, that is to co-ordinate its activities,
must
correspond in structure to that federal nature.
We
have, therefore, to take steps to see that the decisions made
by the state take full account of the interests that will be affected
by those
decisions. Whether the interest affected is individual,
association, or territorial unit, it must be adequately and
effectively
represented in the making of the sovereign will. Wherever there is
a real interest in the community, means must
be found for eliciting
the will of that interest before it is presented with a decision
about
itself by which the contours of its life will be changed. The
organization of the sovereign power, that is to say, must, if it is to
be adequate, be immensely
more complex than in the past It
cannot legislate about trade unions or churches being compelled
so to consult trade unions or churches that their will is fully known
to it before it makes its solution of the problem before it. The
sovereign power must
be compelled, a priori, to make a
comprehensive effort to embody the wills of those over whom it
rules in its will before it is entitled to act upon them. Anything
less
than this is not truly a &ch1sstaat for anything less than this has
not
truly sought that amplitude of knowledge without which, in any
real way, demand cannot be satisfied at its maximum. Anything less
than this means a failure to take into account the conditions of
that successful co-ordination by which alone the authority of the
state can
hope for justification. Only in the degree that this is
attempted can the state be called true to the law of its being.
I have
elsewhere attempted to describe the kind of institutional
pattern to which such a sovereign power must conform.[3]
Here I [**212] can only say that, as a pattern, it seeks
to build into the form of the
state that reality outside by which the success of law-making
is
determined. Those who seek to retain the classic theory of
sovereignty in new form are ready, it appears, to accept the view
that the organization
of its instruments stands in need of
thoroughgoing revision.[4]
They realize that a legal claim cannot
hope for the validation of fact except by genuinely meeting the needs it
encounters. They see that the historic formulae of
representative government
whether in its parliamentary or
congressional form are no longer adequate to the kind of society in
which we live. But they make, I think, the mistake of assuming
that the problem is solved when a reconstruction of the pattern
has
taken place, however adequate that reconstruction may be.
They
believe that there is some mechanism for making sovereignty an
expression of what Rousseau termed the general will of the
community.
That
belief, I suggest, is profoundly mistaken for the simple
reason that there
is no general will in the community at all. We
never encounter any will that can be denominated good by definition. We do
not, indeed, ever encounter in the community a will the unity of which is
effectively comparable to the unity of will
in a human being. A number of
minds does not become one mind
any more than a wood is a tree or a hive a bee. The will of the state
is the will of certain persons exercising certain powers. This will
cannot be termed general in
the sense that Rousseau gave it,
until we know what it is seeking to do and the motives which underlie its
effort. Its value becomes attached to it as we meet its
nature and declare its character: it is not simply a
priori there. The
will of the state may be made to approach
generality the better it
is organized for that end. But organization as such can never assure it of
generality until we know the purpose to which it
proposes to devote its powers. It is not even decisive that a state
should
announce its will in full conformity with the terms of the
constitution. For before we could declare that it was entitled
to
obedience, we should need to know both the character of the
constitution, on the one hand, and the purpose to which, on the particular occasion,
it was being devoted upon the other.
No
theory, in fact, which seeks to make the transference from
state to government can fail to admit the possible perversion of
power. And no theory which scrutinizes the historical process to [**213]
discover the conditions under which power is usually perverted
can be satisfied to declare the inherent primacy of the state will in any
other than a formal sense until steps have been taken to erect safeguards
against those condition of perversion. If, as I have argued, for instance, each
member of the state has an equal claim with others to well-being, conditions
which are historically incompatible with the realization of that equal claim
must be removed simply because their presence alters the evidence of state
action to the advantage of some special section of the community. The state
becomes an instrument of that section. It has been, in the past, the instrument
of the aristocracy, whether of race or birth, of a particular religion, of a
special class. When the state undertakes to enforce its interpretation of
social need, the validity of that interpretation depends very largely upon the
influences to which those who make it are interpreted. In a state, for
example,
divided; like the modern capitalist state, into a small number of
rich and a large number of poor, that unequal distribution of wealth
inevitably introduces bias into the character of state action. Mutatis
mutandis, the same is true of a community like Russia.
There, the demands the state proposes to satisfy
are the demands which the Bolshevik Party believe it is desirable to satisfy.
That Party has identified its conception of good with the total well-being of
the community. Its interpretation may be made from the
highest motives; but it is a biased interpretation,
which ignores the
factor of consent and assumes that power as such creates right. I
cannot accept that view. I should agree that when a constitution is
built upon the wants of men and
operates so as continuously to
satisfy those wants, it is entitled to obedience.
But this raises the
questions: (a) What is a good constitution? (b) who decides
whether it is good? (c) and who decides whether it is good in
operation? My own view is clear that these questions can only be answered in
terms of the judgement of individual citizens. They are the persons who feel
the results of state action in their lives; they,
therefore, are the only persons who are entitled to pronounce
upon its quality. They make the law valid by consenting to it They
consent to it
as it satisfies their desires. A good law, therefore, is a
law which has, as its result, the maximum possible satisfaction of
desire; and no law save a good law is, except in a formal sense,
entitled to obedience
as such. This view, of course, involves an [**214] empirico-historical
theory of politics. It means that a constitution
is not likely to be good unless men equally co-operate in making it,
and working it, for the simple reason that, historically, classes
and
persons excluded from a share in power are always excluded from
a share in benefit Because, therefore, each citizen is an end in
himself, each citizen must know that his desires are so counted
that, equally with other persons, he has a chance of self-
realization. He is entitled to the conditions
which assure him that
his desires will be counted; and these conditions must be inherent
in the fabric of any state which seeks to present itself as worthy
of
obedience. Where, alternatively, those conditions are absent,
those for whom they are absent
are en tided to deny that the state
is the guardian of their interests; and that denial carries with it a
tide to disobey.
I have
termed this view the pluralistic theory of the state because
it is rooted in a denial that any association of men in the
community is inherently
entitled to primacy over any other
association. Neither legal authority nor width of declared purpose
can give that primacy; tide to it depends always upon performance,
and of that performance individuals are always the judge, because
it is in the quality
of their lives only that it is in fact measurable. It
is objected that this is a doctrine of contingent anarchy, that no
state worthy of the name can be satisfied with a view which leaves
open the possibility of dissent from its will. Such
a state, it is said,
will be, in Madisons phrase, a Government in name
only. But the
objection, after all, is purely formal. Ever since Hume showed that
even the most despotic of governments is ultimately dependent
upon
public opinion, theories have been illegitimate which sought
to confuse legal unity with moral unity. Pluralism is simply an
explicit protest against that confusion. It is an attempt to recover
the individual conscience as the only true source of a law which
claims obedience
from its subjects. It is a recognition that no
jurisprudence can hope for adequacy which separates the idea of
law from the idea of justice. It seeks the content of the
latter
conception in terms of the initial postulate that man is an end in
himself
and, therefore, entitled to the conditions which enable
him to realize himself as an end; those conditions, where
equally
maintained for all, it equates with the idea of justice. It does not
deny the need in society either for rules or for organizations to
maintain those
rules; but it does deny that such a need involves the [**215] concept
of a sovereign state, or the attribution to that state of an
inherent supremacy which enables it to dominate all other
associations in the community. It insists that the right to make
rules
is always conditioned by the quality of the rules that are
made.
To the
critic who points out that someone must define the limits
of authority in the individual and the group, that the sovereign
state is merely a convenient hieroglyphic for this purpose,
the
pluralist has, L conceive, at least two answers. He can argue, first,
that as a matter of history the function of definition is never
wisely
performed unless certain conditions are fulfilled, and, second,
that once sovereignty is
possessed by a state, those who exercise it
in the name of the state always effect the transition from legal
formality to moral right Every government claims that it is wrong
to break the law. To the pluralist that judgement can only be made
when it is known
what law is broken and under what circum-
stances. There are realms of conduct, both individual and
collective, into which, under circumstances, he would deny that
the state has a right to enter. He would not merely question the
wisdom of its entry; he
would go even farther and argue that the
organization of the power under which government operates
ought formally to deny the existence of such a right Seeking, also,
the realization of the individual as an end, he would postulate
the
conditions upon which that realization depends as principles
which the ultimate authority, however organized, must respect,
which, also, under all circumstances it must be powerless to
change. The state, for him, is an organization, like any other,
charged with the performance
of certain functions. He cannot see
that the character of those functions entails the right to
sovereignty. For realism compels him to admit that this is the
entrustment of unlimited authority to ordinary and fallible men.
There are no guarantees possible
that such authority will be justly
used. The need, consequently, is paramount to deny tide to its
possession.
A right
to sovereignty, moreover, does not exist for the sake of
sovereignty; it exists for the ends sovereignty is to serve. A right
to
sovereignty must be correlative with the duty of fulfilling
those
ends. These, as I have said, are in their sum the maximum
possible
fulfilment of desires. The logical inference, therefore, from a right
to sovereignty would be a duty so to organize and exercise the [**216]
sovereign power as to secure the ends for which it exists. To
argue
.that the theory of auto-limitation [by the sovereign] fulfils
this
condition is to miss the point that a will bound only by itself cannot
be conceived as objectively bound; for an obligation
of a form of
conduct which the body obliged can alter at will, and yet never
chooses to alter, either suggests a power outside that body
and
controlling it (in which case it ceases to be sovereign), or suggests
the subordination of the body to
principles inherent in human
personality of which the state will is then the subject.
These
dialectical tangles are unsatisfactory. It is better to say
quite simply that the idea of a sovereign state is at variance with
the
idea of law once that idea is conceived as related to a moral
end.
For any other conception of law makes it unconnected with reason
or good except by its own choice; and would leave unexplained
why that choice should be made. The action of a sovereign state
binds as such without regard
to whether that action fulfils the
obligation to which the state is bound by its inherent character.
The character of such a state proclaims not only in its inability
to
discriminate between right and wrong, but even a positive
indifference between them.
The sovereign state makes positive
law; it does not make a law in which there is any inherent relation
to justice. Such a positive law is merely an expression of power;
power is morally neutral until its substance is examined. Since no
state automatically
wills that by which men ought to be bound, it is
neither necessary nor desirable to accept is sovereign character.
The state must derive its law from principles beyond itself, if
the
character of its policy is to have a morally valid claim upon the
allegiance
of men. In any other context, law is empty of all tide to
consent save the naked assertion of its power to enforce
obedience.
V
Nor
must we omit the international aspect of the problem. The
doctrine of the sovereign state becomes a theory of international
law in two ways.
On the one hand, by the rigorous logic of its
primary assumptions, since law is the will of the state, it is
compelled to insist that no rules of international relations have
the
force of law save as the state consents to them; on the other,
most
largely through the influence of Hegel, by its argument that the [**217]
state is the ultimate embodiment of moral values, it assumes
that
international rules are valid only in so far as the state chooses
to
accept them for its purposes. Since the state is the ultimate
and
highest form that allegiance can take, it either denies altogether
the existence of an international community which is above, or
beyond, states; or it argues that while the mutual life of states may
make such a community, its
rules cannot be binding upon them
since the interests each state protects in that international
community are the highest it can know. To bind the will of the
state, therefore, to an objective international law outside its own
will is both mischievous and
undesirable.
It is
difficult to put in moderate terms the degree to which
either aspect of this doctrine is undesirable. By making the
self-
preservation of the state the highest duty it can know, it insists
that
the state is bound by no rules which it does not regard as
serviceable to that end. International law merely becomes a body
of convenient doctrines which a state is free to reject or accept as
it pleases. It is not bound by any agreements or treaties; it is
not
responsible for any wrong; there are no moral obligations
governing its relations with other states. As an eminent exponent
of this view has pointed out,[5]
its logic demands that right and
wrong be the outcome of the exercise of successful force, and
victory in war is made the true judge of international controversy.
I reject this view of the state claim in the international field
upon
exactly the same grounds as in the municipal. The sovereign state
in international relations is a body of persons making decisions. They have
the legal right to make those decisions; but nothing is,
or can be, a
priori known of the moral quality of the decisions
made
until we know their content. That a state refuses to fulfil a treaty
it
has signed makes it no more valid that it should refuse to accept
its
obligation than that a merchant should refuse to fulfil a
contract
he has freely made. That a state should make war without
provocation no more makes that war just than that a man should
commit an unprovoked murder. A treaty forced upon a defeated
state against
its will is no more right than a contract forced upon
one of the parties to it under consent. The goodness or badness of
law is independent of the parties to it, or of their power. It is
a
function of the substance of law, a judgement upon what some
decision
actually proposes to do. It is no more logical to allow a
state both to make its own law and then judge its validity than it is [**218] to
allow the private citizen to be judge of his own actions. Law must
be objective to the state in the international, as it is objective
to the
individual in the municipal, field. Adequate international
relationships are impossible if, on conflict, law is merely to mean
the rule of the stronger. For that is exactly the divorce of law
from
justice which defeats the whole purpose law is intended to serve.
Nor is
it true to say that international law finds its sanction in the
sovereign will of states.[6]
The recognition of a new state is not
followed by an announcement from that state that it accepts the
rules of international law; nor is it
possible for the new state to pick
and choose between them. To argue, as Oppenheim does, that a
demand for recognition, by Communist Russia, for instance, is to
be taken as an implicit acceptance of the binding force of
international law
is to introduce fiction of a peculiarly unedifying
kind. The facts have to be explained very differently. What we
are
presented with is a system of states equal in the sense that each has
an identical right to the protection of the law. That is a position
inherent in the notion
of states as sovereign; for, logically, once
sovereignty is in question there can be no discussion of superior
and inferior. But this right to equal protection of the law is
obviously incompatible with the idea of law as merely a subjective
state right
which each state imposes on others if it will or can. Law
here must mean an objective body of principles above all states,
laying obligations upon them they have no legal alternative but to
accept The very fact, indeed, of a need for recognition
means that
states cannot, in the international sphere, make or unmake law as
they please. But the power to make or unmake law is what the
formal theory of jurisprudence means by sovereignty, and if this
power be absent in states it cannot be claimed
that they are
sovereign.
Or let
us take a doctrine like the famous maxim pacta sunt
servanda. The
classic theory of sovereignty says that this rule is
binding because states will to observe it, and they are equally free
to refuse to will its observance if they so please.
If we ask why states
so will it as law we are told that it is because of the difficulties
to
which any other attitude would give rise. But that is an explanation
which formal jurisprudence is not entitled to adopt. It can only say
that
the rule is binding independently of the will which accepts it,
or the causes which make for acceptance. The will is in fact binding
from its inherent nature. It is an objective norm of a legal order [**219]
which must be postulated as underlying all states and providing
them
with the principles by which their life is lived. To say that
states break the rule no more deprives it of its validity than the
law
against murder is rendered invalid because a man commits
murder. Any other hypothesis, as Bluntschli saw long
ago, would
make international law not merely an inferior kind of contract, but
one in which no agreement was ever binding when a state changed
its mind, and in which, as he said, a change in the states
will
produced a change in the law. Such an outlook results in impossible
contradictions. Jurisprudence must be subject, not less than
other sciences, to the maxim that no more causes are to be
predicted than are necessary to explain the phenomena. To
make
international law the creature of the sovereign states will
is to pile
the Pelion of fiction upon the Ossa of undemonstrable assumption
to a degree that is intolerable.
The
difficulties of the lawyer who insists that international law is
merely the will of the state in the external field are by no means
over
even at this point The whole history of the practice of
international arbitration is the history of the adoption by tribunals
of rules of international law the source of which cannot, even by
the wildest use of fiction, be found in the will
of the state. Phrases
that desire a decision to be made in accordance with principles
of
justice, or considerations of equity, or, again,
on the basis of
respect for law, all clearly indicate that
the idea of law is, for
international purposes, outside and not inside the
states will. Nor,
moreover, can one read the Statute of the Permanent Court of
International Justice without seeing that its underlying assumption
is the notion that the absence of a fixed rule
must not mean a
refusal to judge. The business of the Court is not to
pronounce
itself without jurisdiction, where the will of states is
undiscoverable, but to make a suitable rule in terms of
alternative
sources which can only be explained as valid on the hypothesis
of
objective norms sanctioning inferences of the widest character
in
terms of the needs of an international legal order above
individual
states.[7]
Nor
need we accept the view that only states can be the subjects
of international law. The post-war world is littered
with
organizations which are certainly not subject states, but,
equally
certainly, are the subjects of international law. This is an
antiquated view which flows from the assumptions of formal [**220]
jurisprudence and not from the facts of international life.
International law has to concern itself with the rights and duties of
the League of Nations, of international unions, of the members of
the British Commonwealth of Nations, of pirates, of rebels who
are
recognized as belligerents, none of whom possess the formal
indicia of statehood. It is by no means inconceivable that, in the
future, we shall see individuals recognized as possessing an
international status, able, for instance, to sue a state that has
done
them wrong in an international court. International law
is
theoretically capable of laying rights and duties upon men as well
as upon states; the present conception arises only from the way in
which its foundations have been formulated and not from its
inherent nature. For it is equally
as valid to postulate the existence
of an international community the character of whose law requires
that every person who acts internationally shall be a subject of the
law of that community as to postulate a society of states in which
no persons
save states shall be recognized as the subjects of rights
and duties. The present system is a deposit of historic
categories
invented to explain a given body of facts. It is no more valid for all
the facts we encounter, or all the needs we have to meet, than
Euclidean geometry
is valid for the total universe of geometry.
At this
point, indeed, we can go farther. International law has
been built upon the idea of the state as a legal personality the will
of which embodies a will compounded from the separate wills of
all its subjects.
Now this view of the state is metaphorical only, since
the state itself can act only through persons. When we take a
community politically organized into a state the will of that state is
the will of the person or persons entitled to
act in its name. There
is not a single will in any other sense than that of a legal
capacity
attaching to some persons and not to other persons. From the
angle of an international community concerned to maintain law as
the inherent expression of its ultimate
nature the will of the state
must be a will for that law; a will against it cannot be legal in
any
sense which is valid. For that would mean a right in the state to will
the absence of law, to overthrow the system of jural relations in
which it is necessarily
involved by the fact of being a state. From
this angle it must follow that legal supremacy belongs to the body
of rules which make up international law, and that the rules of any
other society are of lesser significance than these. The state, that is
to say, is bound
in the rules it makes by the superior rules of the [**221] international
community to which it belongs. It cannot make and
unmake them any more than the individual can make or unmake
the law of the state of which he is a subject The personality of the
state is, so to say, an inference from the fact that it is a part of
the
international community. It is a way of conferring legal capacity
upon certain persons within a juridical community to enable them
to formulate rules which have no
validity if they conflict with the
fundamental rules of the society in and through which its capacity
arises. A state, therefore, cannot legally will what it pleases; it
can
only will what is consistent with the superior will of the
international community.
Its personality is a capacity in its rulers
to act for that end, but for no other end.
From
this, I infer the supremacy of international law over the
law of any given individual state. I assume that a jurisprudence
which seeks to be scientific has no alternative but to regard
the
community of states as what has been termed a civitas maxima,
the
law of which is primary over all other law.[8]
States, in this
conception, appear to me as provinces of this civitas
maxima whose
authority is derived from the rules discovered to be
necessary for
the maintenance of the common international life. Apart from
this
conception, J see no way of arriving at a body of axioms capable
of
explaining the relationship between states assumed to be equal
in
international intercourse. No state can have a legal right
to
enforce its will upon another state if both are sovereign; force in
the international sphere can only be valid upon the assumption
that there is a body of legal rules over and above both to which
each equally conforms.
A state is then entitled to force in order
that the legal rules may be maintained. Any other view must
assume ultimately that force makes law; that what is alone valid in
the international sphere is the rule of the strongest which is in
fact
law. I have already rejected this view as incompatible with the
facts,
especially with the doctrine of recognition, in international relations.
International law cannot be, as Hegel argued, merely an
external municipal law, since it would then be changeable, as it is
not,
at the will of each individual state. It is not merely, as
Austin
suggested, a positive morality, since it is the rules of a
society
which, even if more loosely and feebly organized than the state, is,
in Westlakes phrase, as
necessary to human existence as the state
itself.[9]
Right and wrong are notions relevant to the relationship between states, and
such notions predicate the existence of a [**222]
society of which those states are a part. But a society without law
is
inconceivable. The norms, therefore, of that society are
the
necessary rules of its intercourse for the realization of right and
the
avoidance of wrong. The universality of this international
society
presupposes the primacy of its norms over those of its parts. The
state, therefore,
is a subject of law which presides over its being and
limits the nature of the objects it can seek to attain.
VI
In the
light of this conception let us return to the formal theory of
law on its internal side. Law, it is maintained, is the will of
the
sovereign state; and the will of the sovereign state is law because
it
knows no superior. For jurisprudence, therefore, the content of
law, the nature of the norms made by the state, is irrelevant. What
it is concerned with is capacity
to act, not what that capacity
actually does. Any attempt to go beyond this view belongs not to
the field of jurisprudence, but to politics, or morals, or psychology.
No questions in these realms can, it is held, affect the validity of
the
formal conceptions of law. It is, indeed, even claimed that
this
methodology will have the desirable result of removing confusion
from political theory.
I
suggest that this is an entirely mistaken point of view. Were
the
categories of formal law axiomatic in the sense of being
inescapably
necessary to the structure of a scientific jurisprudence
the problems they involve might assume a different character. But,
in fact, they have an origin which is meaningless apart from a
system of special historic conditions in Western Europe,
and they
only partially summarize those conditions. They make
the
construction of a philosophy of law impossible because they refuse
to consider the relation of law to the totality of circumstances
under which it must operate; they omit from their equations
all the
problems to answer which it is in fact necessary to construct a
science of law. They refuse to consider the problems of conflict
and valuation. They see no meaning in the grave issues which arise
from the choice of a point of departure, and
the application to life
of its results. The validity of their results, therefore, holds only of
a
static world in which there are no stresses and strains with
consequences which exist and alter life. If ethical conceptions
have
altered the law, if economic change has meant its adjustment, law [**223] cannot
neglect either ethics or economic change. It is the static
character of the formal theory of sovereignty which explains
its
helplessness before the phenomena of international law; these it
can only resume by the invocation
of fictions utterly unconnected
with reality. The formal theory, indeed, is like the relation between
the ceremonial and the operative parts of the British Constitution.
The King may ride in the carriage, but it is the Prime Minister on
the pavement who
effectively makes the decision. A theory of the
state which emphasizes formality at the expense of substance is not
likely to possess final value. It abstracts the legal system from
the
context in which alone its meaning can be found.
Formal
jurisprudence, therefore, is an answer to the problems
of power existing at any given time; and even to that it is only a
partial answer. The categories it employs are those which
enabled
effective demand to be satisfied roughly since the Reformation;
but there is no
sort of certainty that they will continue to provide
that satisfaction. The new facts of a world order both in the legal
and in the economic sphere are making our political conceptions
rapidly obsolete for the purposes they have to fulfil; and
formal
jurisprudence has been built by its makers in terms of
those
conceptions. Men live to satisfy demands, and they recognize as
valid only the institutions capable of their effective satisfaction.
Our system was constructed, by men like Bodin and Hobbes,
and
Hegel, at a period when the hinterland between states was not
only
not organized but was not unnaturally deemed incapable of
organization. Our whole theory of the state has accordingly been
conceived upon the assumption that it was the final form
of
institutional pattern, and even a body like the League of
Nations
was constructed by men faithful, in the main, to that ideal.
The
facts, I suggest, have outgrown this view, and the
developments require the construction of a new juristic edifice.
The institutional pattern
we need for an adequate theory of
politics must take regard to the demands which require
satisfaction and the way in which that satisfaction is to be
attained.
Here, surely, the unity we have to consider can only be properly
understood
in terms of the universe of facts to which it is relevant.
If miners in England demand an adequate wage, it is the
international coal problem and not the national that we must seek
to compass. Stable financial conditions in London are a function
of Chicago
and Calcutta, of Berlin and Tokyo. These interrelations [**224] have
to be organized in order that we may render satisfaction to
those who live by their results; and the inference that must be
drawn here from is the need for a political philosophy, not in terms
of the
nation-state as the final source of unity but of a cosmopolitan order in which
the nation state is being rapidly reduced by
the facts to the position of an uneasy and unsatisfactory province.
The solutions made by the law-making body in any given
state will
only work in even the national sphere if they fit the facts of
this
cosmopolitan order. They have no assurance of adequacy save as
they are built upon the working consent of at least its major part.
The
inference from this is, I think, of supreme importance for
a working theory of law. The epoch of Grotius, so to say, is drawing
to a close. Instead of building up the conceptions of international
law from the relation of states one to another, we shall, in the
future, have to built up national
law as a system of inferences from
the rules of an international law far wider in its incidence than
national law can claim to be. It is not likely, in this new world,
that
any state will have, even formally, ultimate powers: it will be much
more akin
to the province of a federation, having authority over a
defined sphere, but finding that its powers beyond that sphere
are
strictly limited. England, for instance, may well discover that while
it may prescribe the penalties for murder, it cannot control the
hours of work
for miners; that while it may make its own traffic
regulations, it cannot settle the scale of its tariffs. The process
of
government, in a word, has escaped from the categories in which
the nation-state sought to imprison it. Some part of its
functions,
at least, is obviously destined to transference to a new authority
by
whose commands the nation-state will be bound. It will lack, from
the very nature of the cosmopolitan order, the power to make
final
decisions in any sphere save that allotted to it by the needs of
that
order. It will fail to correspond to the formulae of classical jurisprudence,
and new formulae will be developed more
adequate to the needs jurisprudence must meet.
This
indicates, I venture to think, that the approach to law
cannot usefully be
made in any terms which postulate the state as
its ultimate source. Law is the operative satisfaction of
effective
demand, and its sources are as varied as life itself. The state is
the
organ through which the government registers the fact that some
given demand has secured a factual title to satisfaction: it is
an
announcement that behind this given demand there lies, [**225]
prospectively, the coercive power of society. But, clearly, the
state
is no more than the form such registration now assumes. There
is
no a priori necessity that it should assume this
particular form and
no other form. That depends upon the character of social
organization at the time when some effective demand searches
for
satisfaction. And the value of approaching the problem from
this
angle is that we are not compelled by our definition to put the
orders of the government into a category different from the orders
of other organizations. We learn to see them, as we ought to see
them, as species of a wider genus.
Any association which issues
orders to its members makes law for them which differs in degree
rather than kind from the laws made in the name of the state. The
power, also, of other associations is a power it is difficult
to
differentiate, again except in degree, from that of the state. It
may
be granted that the authority of the state is utilized to make its
orders binding upon all within its jurisdiction: it seeks, within
that
jurisdiction, universality. But we must be careful not to mistake
the
character of that universality. It is a universality simply of
formal
reference. It makes unity upon the ground that unity in some
given realm of conduct is held by those who operate the machinery
of state to be desirable. It does not tell us why it is so held; it does
not tell us
whether its recipients will so regard it and it does not,
finally, tell us whether it ought so to be regarded. Yet a true
philosophy of law ought to explain all these things if it is to satisfy those
over whom its sanctions operate.
A
theory of law, in fact, which does not start by postulating an
end for law, can never explain why law ought to be obeyed; and
there is, surely, no point in making rules except upon the
assumption that they are entitled to obedience. If we assume that
law is
made in order to satisfy human demands at that maximum
which is socially possible we have at least a criterion by which to
create an effective system of values. Therefrom we can infer a
pattern of institutions which, at any given moment of historic time,
enables
us to explain the character of their operation. Such a
theory of law has the merit of escaping subordination to the state.
It attaches values to the institutions which satisfy its purpose, and
to no other institutions. It explains why associations live
and die,
for it shows that their life is set by their ability to satisfy
effective
demand. It does not perish in the formalism of that categorical
hierarchy which makes the state ultimate either on legal or on [**226] moral
grounds. It makes the state ultimate only when its activity enables maximum
demand to be satisfied. But it insists, as the facts
insist, that maximum demand may be satisfied only by refusing
obedience to the state, or, conceivably, by going beyond it to a cosmopolitan
order which must make the rules if demand is to
hope for satisfaction.
This is, of course, a pluralistic theory of law. It is so because the facts
before us are anarchical. We reduce them ourselves to order
by being able to convince men that some unity we make means
added
richness to their lives. We encounter everywhere not
allegiance, but allegiances in men. We are not warranted in
seeking their reduction to a Procrustes-like unity which is formal
only in character. An institution cannot seriously expect to be obeyed merely
because it is an ultimate point in a series where that series itself is a
merely logical construction. Institutions can only
secure obedience in terms of the values that obedience creates;
and if the values are denied by those in whose lives they are to be
effective in
the long run, obedience will be denied also. From this
angle, in short, we can make the necessary bridge between the
formal demands of law, and those other contexts, ethical,
economic, political, psychological, which give the abstract legal
claim its validation
in the event. Above all, such a view as this puts
the source of law where it most truly belongs, in the
individual
consenting mind. For we each of us judge the commands we
receive by their relation to our experience of life; and the success
of the institutions
which formulate commands is a function of
their ability to convince us that their response to that experience
is continuously and deliberately creative.
[1] Mcllwain (1939)
Sovereignty, in Constitutionalism in a Changing
World
[Cambridge: Cambridge University Press]; Coker (1921) American
Political Science Review 15 (2): 86-213; Elliott (1928) The Pragmatic Revolt
in Politic [New York: Macmillan], passim.
[2] Farrand Records of the
Federal Convention, iii, 537.
[3] Cf. Laski (1925) A
Grammar of Politics [London: Allen &
Unwin], chapter 7, passim.
[4] Cf. Elliott op. cit.,
especially the last chapters.
[5] Kaufmann (1911) Das Wesen
des Völkerrechts [Tübingen: J.C.B. Mohr].
[6] See all this put admirably
in Lauterpact (1927) Private Law Analogies in International Law [London: Longmans, Green & Co.], chapter 2. I cannot
overemphasize my debt to this brilliant monograph the
most
significant British contribution to post-war international law.
[7] Cf. L.auterpacht, op. Cit.,
pp. 215ff.
[8] Cf. Kelsens
famous monograph Das Problem der Sauveränität, second edition (1923) [Tübingen: J.C.B. Mohr].
[9] Westlake (1914) Collected Papers in Public
International Law [Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press], p. 13
Reprinted in: Paul Q. Hirst, ed., The Pluralist Theory of the State, pp. 195-227 (1989)