NILQ 71 2 (261)
1 August 2020
Northern Ireland Legal Quarterly > 2020, Volume 71 > Issue 2, August > Articles
Northern Ireland Legal Quarterly
Paul
F Scott
University
of Glasgow
© Queen's University Belfast 2020
Abstract: The British Empire is treated as a historical
phenomenon, but it enjoys a residual existence in the form of the various
Overseas Territories of the UK. This paper considers the constitutional
position of those territories. It shows that they are mostly excluded from what
is called here the 'domestic' constitution, having no representation in its
institutions and, when acknowledged, if at all, conceived of as foreign
entities. Instead, the Overseas Territories are governed mostly via a distinct
(post-)imperial constitution, primarily via the mechanism of the Privy Council.
That institution, which does little work within the domestic constitution,
creates a formal divide between the domestic and the imperial. This formal
divide both masks the substantive continuities between the domestic and the
imperial constitutions and facilitates, as regards the Overseas Territories,
forms of governance which would not be tolerated in the imperial centre.
Keywords: empire; Privy Council; Overseas Territories; orders in council.
Introduction
The
end of the British Empire is usually dated to the handover of Hong Kong to
China in July 1997, but the UK retains a number of Overseas Territories (OTs)
which are best understood as the residue of that Empire: wholly distinct from
the UK itself but for a number of reasons unlikely to join many of the former
colonies of the British Empire in achieving independence, at least in the near
future.1 This article considers how this residue of Empire is
managed constitutionally, arguing that the answer is to be found in the oft-neglected
institution of the Privy Council. The Privy Council, which considered from the
perspective of what is called here the 'domestic' constitution – that of the UK
itself – is something of a black hole, is doubly central to the management of
the residue of Empire. On one hand, the Privy Council is a key formal mechanism
of governance (understood broadly) for the OTs, which keeps that governance
separate from the institutional apparatus with which students of the domestic
constitution are intimately familiar: Parliament, the executive, the domestic
courts.
Simultaneously,
however, the Privy Council acts as a constitutional firewall separating that
domestic constitution from the constitution of the residual British Empire.
That is, the Privy Council ensures a formal (but not substantive) separation of
the domestic and imperial constitutions. For the most part, the judges who
decide disputes from the OTs are those who sit in the Supreme Court, but they
do so not in that capacity but rather as members of the Judicial Committee of
the Privy Council (JCPC). Similarly, within the domestic constitution the
territories are legislated for not usually by the Crown in Parliament but
rather the Crown in Council: the same individuals who comprise the UK's executive
make policy for the territories, but they make it not as ministers of the Crown
but as members of the Privy Council. Rather than it being a matter of pure
formality, or bare arcana, therefore, a key effect of the ongoing existence of
the Privy Council is to create an artificial divide between the domestic and
the imperial constitutions which both hinders the normal processes of
democratic accountability and works to conceal the residue of the British
Empire from the view of those who study the domestic constitution. The
implication of this account is that reckoning with the Privy Council and its
role in the British constitutional order is both necessary and difficult
precisely because to do so involves reckoning with the legacy, and indeed the
ongoing reality, of the British Empire.
1 The residual empire in the domestic constitution
Before
turning to the specific role of the Privy Council, it is necessary to consider
the nature of this residue of the British Empire and how the constitution of
the UK – the domestic constitution – acknowledges and manages (or fails to
acknowledge and manage) this artefact. The residue in question includes 14 OTs:
Anguilla; Bermuda; the British Antarctic Territory; the British Indian Ocean
Territory (BIOT); British Virgin Islands; Cayman Islands; Falkland Islands;
Gibraltar; Montserrat; Pitcairn Islands; St Helena; Ascension and Tristan da
Cunha; Turks and Caicos Islands; and the Sovereign Base Areas (SBAs) of Akrotiri and Dhekelia on the island of Cyprus.2
The position of the territories in the UK's constitutional order is not only
inadequate, but works both to exclude them from constitutional consciousness
and, when that fails, to mislead as to their constitutional status.
Of
the various ministers within the Foreign and Commonwealth Office (FCO), the
Minister for the Commonwealth, UN and South Asia has the greatest level of
involvement with the territories, enjoying responsibility for all of the OTs
except the Falklands, Gibraltar and the SBAs in Cyprus.3 The
Falklands and Gibraltar are the responsibility of the Minister of State for
Europe and the Americas.4 The SBAs, previously said to have been
'run as military bases, not colonial territories' and for that reason
'administered by the Ministry of Defence, and not the
Foreign and
Commonwealth
Office, which administers other Overseas Territories',5 are now
listed amongst the responsibilities of the same minister as are Gibraltar and
the Falklands. This division between different ministers not only has the
effect of implying a hierarchy between the territories – why are most lumped in
with the Commonwealth, UN and South Asia even when located very far from there,
but others given a more accurate geographical representation? – but also means
that the interests of the OTs qua OTs are not represented holistically within
government. Though they are culturally and geographically disparate, with
significant and perhaps often overwhelming interests of their own, the OTs are
nevertheless a single constitutional phenomenon, and the arrangements by which
they are represented within the UK's government obscure that fact. From the
point of view of the territories themselves, however, the problem is a more
fundamental one: that it is the FCO – having inherited the responsibilities of
the Colonial Office – which deals with them rather than, say, the Home Office:
Many people question the very fact that the FCO is the primary interface between the UK and its Territories. This stems from the fact that Montserrat and the other Territories are legally British Territories and populated for the most part by British citizens. As such, Montserrat is neither foreign nor Commonwealth.6
The matter is of long-standing concern to the territories but has resurfaced recently in the context of a consideration of the OTs by the Foreign Affairs Committee, in the process of carrying out its first major inquiry into the position of the OTs for more than a decade.7 It is no merely formal point, but it demonstrates very neatly the manner in which the domestic constitution takes every opportunity to place the OTs out of sight and so, politically, out of mind. On the basis of such sentiments, the Foreign Affairs Committee has recently recommended that the government 'commission an independent review into cross-government engagement with the OTs and the FCO's management of its responsibilities towards them'. The review, it suggested, 'should consider alternatives to the FCO and assess the costs, benefits and risks associated with moving primary responsibility for the OTs away from the FCO'.8
This,
though telling, is by no means the only problem in relations between the centre and the periphery. The Westminster Parliament,
though no longer thought of as an imperial parliament, continues to enjoy
absolute legislative power over the territories, even those in which there
exist domestic democratic institutions. Though it 'tends' only to legislate in
areas such as national security and foreign affairs (described by the Foreign
Affairs Committee, in a misleading allusion to the modern devolution
settlements, as 'reserved' to the UK), there is no legal limit upon Parliament
legislating upon those topics which are, by contrast, 'devolved'. It will
though normally do so only when the OTs in question consent to it doing so.9
As with the more constitutionally prominent question of the relationship
between the Westminster Parliament and the devolved administrations within the
UK, much tension is missed by a bare statement of this position. The key modern
example is the Sanctions and Anti-Money Laundering Act 2018, which permits
the
Foreign Secretary to impose upon the territories (by order in council) publicly
accessible registers of beneficial ownership should the territories fail to
establish such register themselves by the end of 2020.10 This, it
has been noted, is a measure which is understood differently by the UK and the
territories, with the former arguing that what the latter see as a purely
internal matter in fact implicates issues of both foreign policy and national
security.11
Even
when the system operates without controversy, however, there is of course a
major difference between the devolved nations and regions and the OTs. The
people of the former are represented in the Westminster Parliament which
retains ultimate sovereignty over them, while the latter are not represented
either directly or indirectly.12 This too is, predictably, a source
of frustration for the territories:
The Overseas Territories have no direct representation in Parliament which has ultimate authority over its affairs and can pass any law that can impact the Overseas Territories disproportionately … A modern relationship requires each OT with a representative government to have direct representation in a body that, until independence is obtained, can make any law it pleases. There was great support for the Overseas Territories legislatures to have a veto power over laws passed by the British Parliament affecting them directly in the same way that English MPs have a veto power over laws passed affecting England.13
This reference to the 'English votes for English laws' system effectively sets the bar even higher than does implicit analogising with the position of the devolved institutions. MPs representing, say, Scottish constituencies enjoy (unlike those representing England) no ability to veto within the parliamentary process a hypothetical Bill relating to devolved matters in Scotland. But no matter where exactly the bar is set, the basic point is that there is no need to decide exactly how to balance the views of those representing the interests of the periphery against the views of those representing the interests of the centre within the legislative process, for as things stand the former are not formally represented at all.14 There is no logical or practical bar to such inclusion, which occurs in other post-imperial states.15 But nor is there any serious suggestion that this might be done, in the short term or at all. The result is that the political concerns which are taken up by the UK are not necessarily those which are most important to the people of its territories, while there are
occasional
projects to impose rules on the territories without regard to their local
popularity.16 These sorts of decisions will always have an arbitrary
appearance while the processes by which the OTs can feed into central
decision-making are so weak. Though the UK presents itself as a post-imperial
state, it retains a degree and form of control over the territories that
suggests otherwise.
In
its recent report on the OTs, the Foreign Affairs Committee made only the most
anodyne of recommendations in response to this absence of political
representation, saying that:
… the time is right to give serious consideration to establishing a formal mechanism by which members of the Foreign Affairs, Justice, International Development, EFRA and other relevant Committees are able collectively to scrutinise the UK Government's administration of, spending on and policies towards the OTs.17
While such a move might – or might not – improve the quality of accountability for the administration of the OTs to Parliament, it would do nothing to address the fact that the residents of those territories, though mostly British citizens, are not represented either directly or indirectly in a Parliament which enjoys absolute legal sovereignty over them. This is of particular concern given that in many of the OTs those who do not possess some legal status particular to each territory – often described generically as 'belongership' – will not be entitled to vote in elections to the territories' representative institutions, even when they are British citizens or British OT citizens who are permanently resident in the OT in question.18 Those who are not 'belongers' are doubly disenfranchised, represented neither in the institutions which exercise day-to-day control over them nor in those of the UK in which ultimate sovereignty resides. Such deviation from the precepts of democracy would not be tolerated within the domestic constitutional order.
The
overall effect, therefore, is that the position of the OTs within the
institutions of the domestic constitution is, though in the modern era mostly
stable, undeniably inadequate. From the point of view of the territories, this
is unfortunate: their interests are poorly represented within both the
executive and legislative branches of the UK, notwithstanding that the power it
enjoys over them. Though some in the territories would prefer to resolve the
anomaly by acquiring greater autonomy rather than by acquiring greater input
into the decision-making of the imperial centre,
desire for full independence from the UK is mostly limited and such
independence is unlikely to be forthcoming.19 Some of the
territories are unviable as independent states, while others are of such
strategic importance that for the UK to voluntarily cede sovereignty is
unthinkable.20 And the territories are not the helpless victims of
the UK: though there is in general no
funding
of the OTs, most benefit quite substantially in more or less tangible ways from
the relationship. From the perspective of the UK the effect of the status quo –
the incorporation of the OTs into the domestic constitution either as though
they were foreign bodies (made the responsibility of the FCO and given no
representation in the legislature) or not at all – is similarly mixed. The UK
is capable of exercising authority over these territories without allowing them
any direct input into its decision-making and, indeed, does so where the
circumstances are thought to demand it. At the same time, however, the OTs are
willing and able to make use of the practical latitude which they enjoy in
order to act in ways which are potentially harmful to the interests of the UK:
the tax haven status of several of the territories – viewed by them as a matter
of purely internal significance – is the obvious example. In such a way, the
status of the OTs reveals itself to be double-edged, disadvantaging not only
the territories but also at times the metropole.
For
present purposes, however, what matters are not the questions of which set of
interests are to be privileged and where the balance of convenience lies in
relation to the territories individually or collectively. What matters are the
reasons for which these questions go mostly unasked; that is, the ways in which
the UK is able to remain an Empire without being required to acknowledge that
fact directly within its constitutional order. Central to this situation is the
institution of the Privy Council, the constitutional firewall which operates to
separate, more or less successfully in its different guises, and in appearance
much more than in reality, the domestic constitution from its imperial
counterpart.
2 The Privy Council
The
Privy Council is a black hole at the centre of the
British constitution. Any attempt to explain its functions tends towards
vacuity. For example, the Cabinet Manual
informs the reader that the Council 'advises the Sovereign on the exercise of
the prerogative powers and certain functions assigned to the Sovereign and the
Council by Act of Parliament'.21 This practical nothingness
contrasts with, and may in fact be thought to reflect, the richness of the
Privy Council's history. That history is longer than that of most of the
institutions which have usurped it within today's constitution, the Council
being a continuation of the Royal Council – the Curia Regis – through which governmental power was exercised in the
years following the Norman Conquest.22 Dicey, noting that the role
and functions of this Council had been characterised
in a range of – to modern eyes – inconsistent ways, argued that such 'apparent
inconsistency … vanishes on closer inspection, and throws great light on
mediaeval history':
For the 'Curia Regis' possessed every attribute which has been ascribed to it. It was the executive. It was also a Law Court. It certainly took part in acts of legislation. Still, at the time of its existence it was no anomaly, since to the men of the eleventh century, not the combination but the severance of judicial and executive powers would have appeared anomalous.23
Nowadays, and as discussed further below, the most prominent element of the Privy Council is one which has but a minor domestic significance: the decision-making by the
JCPC,
mostly in the context of appeals from a (small, and falling) number of mostly
Commonwealth jurisdictions.24 But the judges who sit on the
Committee are only a tiny minority of the Privy Council, whose members number
upwards of 600.25 They include ministers of the Crown and senior
members of other political parties at Westminster,26 the leaders of
the devolved governments,27 judges of the courts of the various UK
jurisdictions,28 and a small number of Bishops of the Church of
England.29 It is this first category of members which gives the
Privy Council much of its ongoing constitutional significance, for as a matter
of constitutional technicality the Cabinet – that 'hyphen which joins … buckle
which fastens, the legislative part of the state to the executive part of the
state'30 – is a committee of the Privy Council.31 Though
this overlap is of course unusual if not aberrational, each of these categories
is – allowing for certain arcane features of the British constitutional order –
recognisable as belonging to the three standard
branches of the state: legislature, executive and judiciary. In this sense, it
is tempting to simply treat the Council as a legacy of a pre-modern
constitutional order, reflecting – as the Curia
Regis did for Dicey – a period in which the different branches had yet to
develop the separation characteristic of enlightenment constitutionalism, and
notable – if at all – for demonstrating the singular whole out of which our
contemporary, partial, institutions grew. And, certainly, this role is not to
be discounted: the Privy Council's continuing existence does indeed act to
remind modern observers of the fact that whatever rationalist ordering is
perceptible within our constitution was not there to begin with and has as
often been imposed on it from outside as emerged organically from within.
But
several elements of the Council's membership demonstrate that the institution's
present – like its past – goes further than that. One is that the Council is
not merely an external source of advice to the Crown, in whose name power is
exercised, but includes within its composition both members of the Royal family32
and members of the Royal household, most notably the Queen's Private Secretary.33
Another, more relevant for
present
purposes, is that the Privy Council's membership reflects more clearly than
perhaps any other institution of the domestic constitutional order the UK's
imperial past. Amongst the more than 600 members are a number of senior judges
and current or former political actors from Commonwealth states. One survey
suggests that perhaps 10 per cent of the members fall into this category.34
An exhaustive list of those who do so is, however, impossible to provide as the
Privy Council provides only a list of names in, remarkably, alphabetical order
by first name (or, where a counsellor is one form of peer or another, by his or
her title).35 The effect is that, though the names are available,
even the most minimal sense of who many of these people are, and why they have
been appointed to the Council requires further, sometimes even extensive,
research. Amongst those who represent the Commonwealth in one form or another
are Ezekiel Alebua, former Prime Minster of the
Solomon Islands; Doug Anthony, former Deputy Prime Minister of Australia; Owen
Arthur, former Prime Minister of Barbados. Membership of the Privy Council
appears to be limited to political figures from the Commonwealth realms, not
(for obvious reason) encompassing the Commonwealth republics. Not all of the
former, however, appear to be so represented.
It
was noted above how fully the domestic constitution excludes the OTs,
acknowledging them – if at all – only in their capacity as 'other' and not as
part of a persistent empire. Further evidence of this orientation is to be
found in the fact that there does not appear to be direct or systematic
representation of the OTs in the Privy Council, though, for the same reason
that it is difficult to know exactly who is a member of the Privy Council, it
is difficult to be certain that none of the many hundreds of members was
appointed in whole or in part due to his or her relationship with one or
another of the OTs. This intensifies rather than diminishes the problem which
we have identified, for – as we shall see below – of the domestic institutions
it is the Privy Council which exercises the most frequent legislative authority
over the OTs. To be clear: independent countries which have chosen to retain
the monarch as head of state are (mostly) represented on the Council, but
territories for whom it makes law are not. They thus have neither direct nor
indirect representation within the bodies, Parliament and Privy Council, which
still in large part govern them. The Privy Council, it suffices now to note, is
an institution of the UK's constitution, but one which – unlike the domestic
institutions which are an outgrowth of it, and which in the modern world mostly
obscure it – bears, if subtly and without prominence, the marks of the UK as an
imperial power. We see this in a number of ways, almost none of which are –
not, it is submitted, coincidentally – prominent in the modern constitutional
literature, within which the Privy Council features either little or at all.
Though
the Privy Council is poorly served by that literature, we can extract from it a
number of idealised ways of thinking about the body
and its contemporary significance. One comes from the work of Dicey. Like the
majority of the texts which follow it, Dicey's Introduction to the Study of the Law of the
Constitution contains no extended discussion of the Privy Council, but
Dicey had written, early in his career, an essay on the body, which won the
Arnold Prize in 1860.36 Though the essay is largely historical,
Dicey commends the study of that history, which is 'nothing else than the
account of the rise of all the greatest institutions which make up our national
constitution':
Our Parliaments and our Law Courts are but the outgrowth of the Council. In its history is seen how not only institutions but ideas assumed their modern form. As we study the gradual separation of judicial, political, and administrative functions, it is perceived that the notions of 'Law,' 'the State,' and 'the Government,' which now are so impressed on men's minds as almost to bear the delusive appearance of innate ideas, themselves grew up by slow degrees; and that the annals of a past age can never be understood till men have ceased to apply to them terms and conceptions which are themselves the product of later periods.37
This seems true – the Privy Council is the seed from which much, if not all, else grew – and so one question for constitutional lawyers is why it still exists within our constitution: a very obvious relic of constitutional history but not one which has yet been discarded altogether, nor even reduced to an entirely formal role.
Recent
literature has paid significant critical attention to the imperial context of Dicey's writings.38 Considered in that light, it
is notable that, though the history of the Privy Council is told by him up to
the reign of William IV, Dicey has little to say of its involvement in the
governance of the British Empire, though such governance was in the past a
major aspect of its work, much of it through that committee known more formally
as the Lords of Trade and Plantations and more commonly as the Board of Trade.39
Other leading considerations of the modern domestic constitution make little if
any reference to the Council, though it has often been suggested as a possible
solution to some new or newly apprehended constitutional dilemma. J D B
Mitchell, for example, argued that the Privy Council ('and I emphasise that I do not mean the Judicial Committee of the
Privy Council') should be given a new administrative jurisdiction, like that of
the French Conseil d'Etat,
in recognition of the weakness of parliamentary control of administration.40
Tony Benn had earlier argued that it should replace the House of Lords.41
More recent discussion considered whether the monarch, in granting royal assent
to Bills passing both the House of Commons and the House of Lords, was acting
on the
advice
of the executive of the day or the Privy Council, or neither.42
There is then, a sense that when we find ourselves discussing the Privy Council
in its contemporary rather than historical role, something must already have
gone wrong: we must, by definition, be in the realm of (perhaps slightly
fevered) speculation, casting around for a deus ex machina by which one constitutional
anomaly will resolve the problems caused by another.
All
of which is to reaffirm that there is, in the ordinary course of events, a remarkable
lack of attention paid to the Council. Post-Dicey, Sir Almeric
FitzRoy, Clerk to the Privy Council, published a
history of it in 1928.43 A few years ago, David Rogers, a political
advisor (including to William Whitelaw when he was Lord President of the
Council), published a book about the Council.44 That book – by
virtue, it would seem, of its sheer novelty (a novelty on which the book trades
openly) – was reviewed by Martin Loughlin in the pages of the London Review of Books.45
Loughlin contests Roger's implicit endorsement of 'FitzRoy's
claim that the Privy Council triumphantly vindicates Tocqueville's observation
that “forms are the fortresses of liberty”':
This kind of Whiggism overlooks the radical change in the Privy Council's function from instrument of monarchical government in a law-framed constitution to instrument of parliamentary government operating through conventional understandings. Tacitus is closer to the mark. The secret of establishing a new state, he says, is to maintain the forms of the old.46
That is, the Privy Council has contributed to the emergence of modern democracy by providing a stable form within which the underlying substances has been able to evolve. Though both FitzRoy's and Loughlin's claims are superficially plausible, the length of time between their articulation is indicative of the level of attention paid to the Council by constitutional scholars. The resulting gap in our understanding is perhaps best illustrated by the fact that the Interpretation Act 1978 defines 'The Privy Council' in a fashion so circular as to border on the absurd: it means, we are told, 'the Lords and others of Her Majesty's Most Honourable Privy Council'.47
It is
perhaps tempting for the domestic constitutional lawyer to simply note this
lacuna and move on; to explicitly confine the Privy Council to the realm of the
dignified,48 or to go further and to say that though it is
interesting it holds no significance for us as modern constitutional lawyers –
we should pay as much attention to it as we do to, say, the Lord Chamberlain,
or the Lord Keeper of the Privy Seal. Once the question
is
considered from the point of view of the UK as an imperial or post-imperial
state, however, we see that this temptation must be resisted. Regardless of how
it originated, and regardless of what it now means and does not mean for and
within the domestic constitution, the Privy Council reflects very directly
(perhaps, though nothing turns on it, more directly than does any other aspect
of the contemporary constitution) the legacies of the British Empire. To
confront the anomalies of the Privy Council is to confront the UK's unambiguous
imperial past and, more importantly, its ambiguous imperial present. And so,
conversely, the willingness to tolerate the constitutional anomaly of the Privy
Council – the fact that rather than seeking to understand it and to mitigate
some of its more obnoxious features, we (constitutional lawyers, but also the
public more generally) are almost always content to ignore it – indicates the
absence of any felt need to confront that legacy. In the following sections I
make that case by considering the roles that the Privy Council plays in the
governance of the residue of the British Empire, showing – in each case – that
the formal institutional distinctions mask a substantive continuity; that the
Privy Council, and the imperial constitution of which it forms part, is not a
distinct order, but rather the shadow of the domestic constitution.
3 The judicial role of the Privy Council
The
element of the Privy Council which is most familiar to contemporary observers
is the Judicial Committee. Though the Committee was formally constituted only
by the Judicial Committee Act 1833, the principle that statute reflects is much
older:
The practice of invoking the exercise of the royal prerogative by way of appeal from any Court in His Majesty's Dominions has long obtained throughout the British Empire … In the United Kingdom the appeal was made to the King in Parliament, and was the foundation of the appellate jurisdiction of the House of Lords; but in His Majesty's Dominions beyond the seas the method of appeal to the King in Council has prevailed, and is open to all the King's subjects in those Dominions.49
The judicial element of the Council was attested in a variety of other ways: the courts of both common law and chancery were originally elements of the Privy Council, exercising the King's prerogative to dispense justice, and remained that way until replaced by the High Court and the Court of Appeal following the enactment of the Supreme Court of Judicature Act 1873.50 The 1833 Act, which in creating the Judicial Committee reaffirmed that 'from the decisions of various courts of judicature in the East Indies, and in the plantations, and colonies and other dominions of His Majesty abroad, an appeal lies to His Majesty in Council', does not create a judicial body as we would normally understand it. Rather it perpetuates the prior situation in which the judgment of the JCPC is not in fact a legal determination, but rather advice to the sovereign as to the judgment that should be made.51 An Act of 1844 created the power 'to provide for the admission of any appeal or appeals to Her Majesty in Council from any judgments … of any court of
justice
within any British colony or possession abroad'.52 In an evocative
account of the JCPC, Viscount Haldane suggested that its real work was 'that of
assisting in holding the Empire together'.53
That
element of the Committee's jurisdiction which is most prominent is that by
which it acts as a court of final appeal for a number of Commonwealth
jurisdictions, both monarchies (Antigua and Barbuda, the Bahamas, Cook Islands
and Niue (Associated States of New Zealand), Grenada, Jamaica, St Christopher
and Nevis, Saint Lucia, Saint Vincent and the Grenadines, and Tuvalu) and
republics (the Republic of Trinidad and Tobago, Mauritius and Kiribati – the
jurisdiction in relation to the latter being very limited).54
Geographically broad and diverse as these jurisdictions are, this represents a
significantly lesser reach than was once possessed by the Privy Council:
Pollock noted early in the twentieth century that 'no other Court in the world
has a jurisdiction of such variety and complexity'.55 It was 'at its
height' in the period following the First World War, 'at a time when almost all
the Overseas Territories acquired by Great Britain during the period of her
expansion still remained intact as an integral part of the British Empire and
when Great Britain had in addition accepted from the League of Nations a
Mandate for a number of ex-enemy colonies and possessions'.56 Though
the largest of the Commonwealth states have abolished the Privy Council's
jurisdiction thereover – something first made possible by the Statute of
Westminster, which provided that henceforth no Act of a dominion parliament
would be 'void or inoperative on the ground that it is repugnant to the law of
England, or to the provisions of any existing or future Act of Parliament of
the United Kingdom'57 – what remains is nevertheless a very obvious
reminder of the UK's imperial past.58
From
the perspective of the present study, however, another aspect of the JCPC's
work is more directly relevant – that which relates to the UK's OTs,59
including the SBAs
in
Cyprus.60 Where the Committee's Commonwealth jurisdiction reflects
the UK's imperial past, this jurisdiction is better understood as representing
its imperial present. Though it attracts far less attention than does the
jurisdiction over Commonwealth realms and republics, this element of the JCPC's
jurisdiction is by no means marginal. To take first the OTs, the following are
figures for the number of cases relating to these places decided between 2010
and 2019:61
|
|
|
|
|
Year |
No of cases decided |
|
|
2010 |
8 |
|
|
2011 |
4 |
|
|
2012 |
3 |
|
|
2013 |
13 |
|
|
2014 |
11 |
|
|
2015 |
9 |
|
|
2016 |
11 |
|
|
2017 |
7 |
|
|
2018 |
6 |
|
|
2019 |
8 |
|
|
|
|
|
The
number of cases from each OT is as follows:
|
|
|
|
|
Overseas Territory |
No of cases decided |
|
|
Anguilla |
5 |
|
|
Bermuda |
23 |
|
|
British Antarctic Territory |
0 |
|
|
British Indian Ocean Territory |
0 |
|
|
British Virgin Islands |
28 |
|
|
Cayman Islands |
14 |
|
|
Falkland Islands |
0 |
|
|
Gibraltar |
6 |
|
|
Montserrat |
2 |
|
|
Pitcairn Islands |
1 |
|
|
St Helena, Ascension and Tristan da Cunha |
0 |
|
|
Turks and Caicos Islands |
9 |
|
|
Sovereign Base Areas of Akrotiri and Dhekelia |
1 |
|
|
|
|
|
In
2013, the year with the highest number of decided cases from the OTs, such
cases represented more than a third (34) of those decided by the JCPC. This is,
it bears
repeating,
not a marginal or secondary aspect of the JCPC's jurisdiction – indeed, given
the very small populations of most of the OTs, it is probably a much higher per
capita recourse to the Committee than is made by any of the Commonwealth states
for which it continues to act as a final court of appeal.
But
these figures are high not only as a proportion of the JCPC's work. They are
high also as a proportion of the work of the UK Supreme Court, which in that
same year (2013) decided 81 cases. To spell out the obvious: it makes a certain
amount of sense to separate the work of the courts in relation to the
'undivided realm' from that of other states, and so it is not inherently
illogical, considered in historical context, to have two bodies doing such similar
work. It is, however, less obviously reasonable for the OTs to be dealt with by
the latter (the JCPC) rather than by the former (the Supreme Court). Indeed,
this might be thought to be the judicial equivalent of the lamented
arrangements discussed above, whereby the OTs relate to the UK via the FCO
rather than the Home Office. If such a change were made – that is, if appeals
from the OTs went to the UK Supreme Court rather than the JCPC – we could
crudely estimate that they would in at least some years account for more than
10 per cent of the Supreme Court's work. In such a situation, the ongoing
imperial nature of the UK would be far more difficult to overlook than is
currently the case. It would be present on the website of the highest court in
the land (rather than a separate site) and the cases would be tweeted out by it
(the JCPC does not have its own Twitter feed, and the UK Supreme Court's does
not routinely tweet about the judgments of its alter ego).
The
effect, then, is that the Privy Council acts as a constitutional firewall which
separates the UK – the post-imperial state, with a domestic constitution which
is post-imperial – from its reality as an ongoing imperial entity. For, of
course, these are not in substance two different entities: the same individuals
who act as justices of the Supreme Court on one floor of the old Middlesex
Guildhall move to a different floor of that same building to act in their
capacity as members of the JCPC when deciding cases which arrive from the OTs.
The Privy Council is a formal barrier which disguises the substantive identity
of the body at work and allows the UK to maintain two constitutions in
operation simultaneously: one domestic and another imperial.
4 The legislative role of the Privy Council
The
same dynamic which characterises the judicial role of
the Privy Council is evident also in its legislative role in relation to the
OTs: issues of form work to create an artificial divide, disguising the
substantive reality whereby the government of the UK legislates, through the
Council, for a residual empire. The starting point is that the territories in
most cases have representative institutions of their own. Parliament, however –
still an imperial Parliament – retains the unfettered right to legislate for
the territories as and when it sees fit, notwithstanding the lack of democratic
representation therein discussed above. In practice, it does not often do so.
Instead, law is made for the territories by the Privy Council. The formal
legislator is not the 'Queen in Parliament' but rather the 'Queen in Council'.
There
are two primary forms of legislation for which the Queen in Council is formally
responsible. Though both are 'orders in council', one is statutory in nature,
the other prerogative.62 Statutory orders in council are a form of
'statutory instrument' to which
the
provisions of the Statutory Instruments Act 1946 apply.63 The key
consequence of being so designated is that statutory instruments must be
published. That secondary legislation is a statutory instrument does not in
itself determine that it must be laid before Parliament nor the extent (if any)
of parliamentary scrutiny that it undergoes, both of which are determined by
the parent Act. Though they differ in their conception from other types of
statutory instrument – being made by the Queen in Council, usually with the
Lord President of the Council and three other of its members present64
– statutory orders in council do not necessarily raise any great issues of
constitutional principle: Parliament, after all, has empowered their making.
Nevertheless, the use of such orders to legislate for the OTs – even to provide
them with constitutions, which Parliament has in the past not done directly but
rather empowered the Crown in Council to do – is deeply unsatisfactory. In most
cases the relevant orders in council are not subject to the normal processes of
parliamentary scrutiny, and so the requirement that they be printed is the sole
obligation.65 Even in the case of orders in council creating
constitutions for the territories, the usual obligation is solely to lay them
before Parliament, and that does not apply in all cases.66 That
Parliament is denied the oversight role it would ordinarily play in the making
of secondary legislation might be considered less significant in light of
modern understandings of how weak is that oversight, both in its negative and
affirmative forms,67 but the principle must be insisted upon. There
should be scrutiny, guaranteed by law, and yet the forms of the Privy Council
work, very often, to evade that requirement, obscuring a practice that would
not be accepted in other circumstances.68
The
second form of order in council, more significant both for present purposes and
from the point of view of constitutional principle, is the prerogative order in
council.69 Such orders do not fall within the definition of
statutory instruments in the 1946 Act and so are not subject to the rules as to
publication: as discussed further below, they are often not published in a form
accessible to the public at large, or even in some cases at all. Nor, being
non-statutory in nature, can a parent Act impose procedural obligations upon
the legislating body – there is in relation to such orders no parent Act.
Prerogative orders in council therefore can and do come into force without
having been published by Her Majesty's Stationery Office and without Parliament
having been given sight of them, quite apart from being given the opportunity
to scrutinise and perhaps even reject them.
The
scope of what might be done via prerogative order in council in the UK itself
has been severely limited for several centuries. Most authorities trace the
limitation to the decision in the Case of
Proclamations and Coke's dictum that 'the King cannot change any part of
the common law, nor create any offence by his proclamation, which was not an
offence before, without Parliament'.70 Proclamations could only go
with the grain of the existing law, and not against it.71 Such
orders therefore were – and are – in that sense not always truly legislative.
But Coke's dictum, it transpires, applies (at least in its fullest form) only
to England and later the UK. As with the rule in Entick v Carrington,72 the great principles of English
common law are, it would seem, geographically constrained, and the outside –
the OTs included – is constituted as a necessarily inferior 'other'. That is,
amongst those few genuinely legislative acts which might still be done by
prerogative order in council are – crucially – the making of law for the OTs.
Prerogative legislation remains a key tool for the governance of the residual
British Empire notwithstanding that it has dwindled almost to nothing within
the domestic constitution.
The
prerogative encompasses in the first a power to make constitutions for the OTs.
This power has been augmented (rather than placed in abeyance) by statute,73
with the majority of the OTs being subject to constitutions made on the basis
of one or the other statute.74 The points made above about the
procedural deficiencies of many statutory orders in council – not required even
to be laid before Parliament – apply also to orders in council creating
constitutions for those territories where there is no statutory basis for
doing
so; where they are, that is, prerogative orders in council.75 The
OTs in this category are Gibraltar and the BIOT. Their constitutions were made
solely under the prerogative, with the prerogative to make 'ordinary' law
explicitly reserved in the relevant orders. Moreover, a continuing power to
legislate by order in council (deriving 'at least in part' from an Act of
Parliament)76 is reserved in relation to all of the territories
other than Bermuda and the SBAs.77 Without such reservation, as we
shall see shortly, the creation of representative bodies in a territory would
suffice to deprive the Queen in Council of the power to legislate under the
prerogative.
To
explain briefly the position of Parliament and prerogative as regards colonies:
the common law distinguished between those which were settled, to which English
law would apply without further action, and those which were ceded or
conquered, in which existing laws would apply until changed.78 Those
changes might be made by either Parliament or Crown. In Campbell v Hall,79 Lord Mansfield gave an influential
account of the legal position of colonies acquired by conquest, starting from
the proposition that a country 'conquered by the British arms becomes a
dominion of the King in the right of his Crown; and, therefore, necessarily subject
to the Legislature, the Parliament of Great Britain'.80 He emphasised that, though the King was permitted to legislate
for a conquered territory, his legislation was necessarily inferior and subject
to limits which did not apply to Parliament:
… if the King (and when I say the King, I always mean the King without the concurrence of Parliament,) has a power to alter the old and to introduce new laws in a conquered country, this legislation being subordinate, that is, subordinate to his own authority in Parliament, he cannot make any new change contrary to fundamental principles …81
In normal circumstances, therefore, a conquered colony was subject to these dual authorities: one absolute and one limited, however slightly and however imprecisely. In Campbell, however, Mansfield held that, though the King generally had authority to make laws for conquered territories, he had in respect of Grenada handed it over to a representative assembly and a governor. For that reason, a later attempt to impose taxation via the prerogative was void.82 The exercise of the prerogative to empower the legislature to make laws for the colony operated as a ratchet, which could be done but not undone by the Crown. Once so empowered, the local legislature could have its power diminished only by the imperial Parliament.
Once
a colonial legislature existed, the question necessarily arose of the
relationship between its laws and those of England. The basic rule was widely
understood to be that colonial laws were void if 'repugnant' to the laws of
England, though there was significant uncertainty as to the practical meaning
of that rule, and – in particular – whether the law in question included only
legislation of the imperial Parliament or encompassed also rules of the English
common law.83 Lord Mansfield's bare reference, in the passage from Campbell v Hall quoted above, to
'fundamental principles' had muddied the waters, and judges in some of the
colonies were keen to exploit the ambiguity.84 The difficulty was
resolved – in part – by the Colonial Laws Validity Act 1865 (CLVA), whose long
title states its intention as being 'to remove Doubts as to the Validity' of
the laws in question. The Act, for present purposes, does a number of things.
First, it confirms the inferiority of colonial law to the laws of the imperial
legislature, whether primary or secondary.85 From now on, colonial
law was void if 'repugnant' to Acts of the imperial Parliament or their
equivalent, but not otherwise.86 Loose and uncertain talk of
fundamental principles of the common law was no longer a threat to the validity
of laws made by colonial legislatures.
The
meaning of the 1865 Act has been explored in a number of cases, most
importantly Bancoult,
which pertains to (what is now) the BIOT. The territory, often known as the Chagos Islands, was famously (and disgracefully)
depopulated in the 1960s in order to permit the construction of a US naval
base.87 In Bancoult (No 1) it was held that the Immigration
Ordinance 1971 by which that depopulation was effected – made under the British
Indian Ocean Territory Order 1965, a prerogative order in council – was
unlawful. An order in effect exiling the population could not be said to be
made 'for the peace order and good government' of the territory.88
When the government responded with a new order in council – the British Indian
Ocean Territory (Constitution) Order 2004 – it argued that prerogative orders
in council, being acts of the Queen in Council,
were
immune from judicial review. At first instance, the Divisional Court rejected
this, holding that the decision to make the 2004 Order 'was in reality that of
the Secretary of State, not of Her Majesty' and so could be challenged by way
of judicial review 'in the ordinary way'.89 The CLVA, being
concerned only with repugnancy, did not prevent the review of the order on
rationality grounds,90 and the claim that the order was indeed
irrational was accepted by the High Court.91
The
conclusions as to the implications of the 1865 Act were challenged on appeal,
where it was argued that the effect of that Act was that an order in council
applicable to the colonies could be challenged only on the basis of its
repugnancy to an imperial statute and on no other grounds. Crucial here was
that the 'colonial laws' whose status was clarified in 1865 were defined in the
Act to include 'laws made for any colony … by Her Majesty in Council'.92
Sedley LJ was sceptical as to the logic of this
inclusion, suggesting that it was a 'fair inference' that orders in council
'were included by the parliamentary draftsman in the definition of colonial
laws in s 1 for completeness, since they too were a source of colonial law,
with the consequence that they acquired the same limited protection as local
colonial statutes'.93 Nevertheless, the notion of repugnancy was
only a live one when the relevant 'colonial law' was first validly made, and so
the 1865 Act did not preclude a challenge to the validity of the 2004 Order.94
Nor did the subject matter of the order – specifically, the fact that it
related to colonial governance – in itself preclude judicial review: 'one can
readily accept that the colonial use of the prerogative power is for the most
part beyond the reach of judicial review, but not that it is always or
necessarily so'.95 In holding that the 2004 Order was unlawful by
reason of being an abuse of process, the Court of Appeal took the view that it
had been done not in the interests of BIOT, but rather of the UK:
The governance of each colonial territory is in constitutional principle a discrete function of the Crown. That territory's interests will not necessarily be the interests of the United Kingdom or of its allies. This is not to say that the two things are mutually exclusive: they will often, perhaps usually, be interdependent, so that the defence of a colony from attack, and even its use as a base to protect the United Kingdom, may serve both its and the United Kingdom's interests. But that is not the case here …96
On the first point the House of Lords agreed, holding that prerogative orders in council making provision for the OTs are in principle subject to judicial review: the 1865 Act did not immunise them against such review.97 So, too, it is clear, might statutory orders in council be subject to such review.98 Nevertheless, the law lords allowed the appeal of the FCO. First, it held, the Crown's legislative power was plenary, not limited by the traditional formulation of 'peace, order and good government'. To the extent that Bancoult
(No 1) had suggested otherwise, it was wrong.99 Though
it was accepted by all the law lords that some rights might be so fundamental
as to limit the plenary power of the Crown, the majority held that the right of
abode is not such a right. Second, the order could not be invalid for being
contrary to the interests of the Chagossian people,
for there was no obligation to act on their behalf. 'Her Majesty exercises her
powers of prerogative legislation for a non-self-governing colony on the advice
of her ministers in the United Kingdom' said Lord Hoffmann, 'and will act in
the interests of her undivided realm, including both the UK and the colony.'100
What this means in practice is that the interest of the part might be – as they
indeed seem to have been – sacrificed in pursuit of those of another part of
the whole:
Her Majesty in Council is therefore entitled to legislate for a colony in the interests of the United Kingdom. No doubt she is also required to take into account the interests of the colony (in the absence of any previous case of judicial review of prerogative colonial legislation, there is of course no authority on the point) but there seems to me no doubt that in the event of a conflict of interest, she is entitled, on the advice of Her United Kingdom ministers, to prefer the interests of the United Kingdom.101
Though the effect of the Bancoult litigation is to confirm the possibility of legal challenge to prerogative orders in council as they apply to OTs, much more was lost than won. The decision of the House of Lords demonstrates a number of points. First, the emptiness of even the minimal limits implied by the language – common to the instruments governing all of the OTs – of 'peace, order and good governance'. Second, the poverty of fundamental rights discourse as it applies to those territories – entirely compatible, the majority held, with the depopulation of the islands. Third, and more generally, law might be made for those territories, over the head of their inhabitants, in pursuit of the interests of an 'undivided realm' whose centre of political gravity sits many thousands of miles away. The logic at work in this decision is, palpably, the logic of empire.102 And the decision in Bancoult (No 2) – which one would strain to call even a Pyrrhic victory103 – appears even less edifying once we remind ourselves of the underlying position whereby the rules governing such territories can in many cases be made without prior statutory authority and little or no democratic oversight. There is no democratic oversight in the imperial Parliament at Westminster, and none either in the representative organs of the OT in question (if such things even exist). To reaffirm: the power for the Queen in Council to make laws in exercise of the prerogative is reserved in relation to the majority of the OTs. Such orders in council are subject to no procedural obligations vis-à-vis Parliament, while statutory orders in council are in many cases subject only to the requirement that they be published after being made.
The
scale of the practice of prerogative legislation is presumably now small. Its
extent, however, appears difficult and perhaps impossible to discern exactly,
as there are very significant issues relating to the accessibility of
prerogative orders in council, including to those most affected by them; issues
which of course are a direct function of the procedural void in which they are
made. These issues are of such gravity as to perhaps call into question their
status as law. Though it is not unique in this regard, the BIOT case is the
most egregious example given the appalling treatment of the native people by
the UK and the quantity of associated litigation. One study of the case
outlines the position as to the accessibility of the relevant legal rules:
There is no official website with authoritative copies of the legislation. The official government website for legislation has a small number of BIOT statutes, but none made under the Royal Prerogative … The one place that BIOT legislation is published is in the British Indian Ocean Territory Gazette. Once again, the Gazette is not available online. According to the FOI response from the FCO, the current total global distribution list of the Gazette is 20. Of these, 16 go to an emanation of the government. The remaining 4 on the list are all British law libraries … One copy does go to Mauritius, but it is to the British High Commission there.104
Though the point is not always quite so vital as in the context of BIOT, a cursory search will demonstrate that the difficulty of obtaining legislation applies also in the context of the other OTs. The British Library's guide to the research of legislation, for example, says this about prerogative orders in council:
Other instruments, though not SIs, may be included in the annual volumes of these as a kind of appendix. Still others may be issued as parliamentary papers, printed in the London Gazette or reprinted in the British and Foreign State Papers, all of which are indexed. Some may be issued separately but many are unpublished in any form and are available only as original documents at the National Archives, where enrolled copies should be among the chancery records. More recent Orders in Council may be available directly from the Privy Council Office.105
The problem is perhaps worse than this account may suggest, for prerogative orders in council often confer the power to make legislation on the governor in lieu of a legislature. Such ordinances are, of course, subject to even more attenuated political control than are the orders under whose authority they are made, with the intervention of the Queen in Council in relation to the latter acting to distinguish what is merely pseudo-democratic from what is entirely undemocratic.
Even
if one accepts the need to have broad law-making powers in relation to the OTs,
in short, much might be done to improve the status quo. There is, for example,
no reason that the making of such legislation could not be placed in its
entirety upon a statutory footing. And – the previous example shows – this could
easily be done without taking responsibility from the Privy Council, if it was
desired to retain the distinction between what is done by the (UK) executive
and what is done by the Crown in Council. Nor would it be at all onerous to
make prerogative legislation widely and easily available, by – for example –
giving it the status of statutory instruments and so making it subject to the
relevant rules as to publication. The status quo, whereby new prerogative
orders in
council
are published in a messy, unsearchable form on the website of the Privy Council
and older ones have disappeared into a juridical black hole, is completely
intolerable. More ambitiously, but still straightforwardly, the making of
orders in council, both statutory and prerogative, for the OTs might be made
subject to the approval of Parliament. Provision might be made for the
involvement, in some form, of the relevant institutions of the territory in
question. What the Bancoult
litigation shows, however, is that such formal improvements, no matter how
urgent, will only go so far to improve the status quo. The issue of plenary
legislative power for the territories within the prerogative, underpinned by
the logic of an undivided realm is more dangerous, for it neatly encapsulates
both the vulnerability of the territories and the persistence of the deep logic
of empire. The territories are separate when it suits the metropole – as when
it comes to such matters as democratic accountability, or basic rule of law
standards – but part of a single whole when it does not.
It is
also significant that prerogative orders in council are, unlike their statutory
equivalent, primary legislation for the purposes of the Human Rights Act 1998
(HRA).106 On this basis, it was argued in Bancoult that, having equal
status to Acts of the Westminster Parliament, they were immune from review by
the courts. This was – quite rightly – rejected. Whatever their formal status,
prerogative orders in council lack the democratic character of Acts of
Parliament: though such an order 'may be legislative in character, it is still
an exercise of power by the executive alone'.107 But the designation
of these instruments as primary legislation by the HRA has related
consequences: the courts have no power to strike them down, but may only –
where appropriate – make a declaration of their incompatibility with the
European Convention on Human Rights.108 Moreover, a prerogative
order in council may provide a defence for a public
authority which has been required by it – contrary to the general principle
found in section 6 of the Act – to act incompatibly with the Convention rights.109
This notwithstanding that there has been no parliamentary oversight of their
content and no minister has been required to make a statement of their compatibility
with the Convention, as is required of Bills laid before Parliament.110
How, but also if, any incompatibility arising from a prerogative order in
council is remedied is left to others to determine – not Parliament, but rather
the executive, which will be permitted to act unilaterally in framing the
remedy and in putting it before the monarch for approval.
Given
that one significant element of the use of prerogative orders in council
relates to the governance of the OTs, the effect of what appears at first sight
to be a relatively technical point about their status under the HRA reveals
itself to be the potential source of great injustice, allowing the government
of the day to both have its constitutional cake (by not subjecting prerogative
orders in council to any form of direct democratic
oversight)
and eat it (by nevertheless insulating them from fundamental rights challenges
as though they were an expression of Parliament's clear will). It would be
reasonable to identify, once more, a certain constitutional contempt for the
OTs, again both given effect but also simultaneously hidden from domestic view
by the institution of the Privy Council. To repeat the point made above in the
relation to the judicial role of the Council: these legislative powers are not
being exercised by the Privy Council in its entirety, with its absurdly large
and eclectic membership. They are being exercised by the government of the day,
the formal constitutional distinction serving most obviously to disguise the
substantive continuity. The form of the Privy Council works to create an
artificial separation between the domestic order and that which is the residue
of empire, hiding the latter from public view and, in the legislative case,
providing cover for practices that the domestic constitution would rightly
reject.
Conclusion
It is
not for nothing that the Privy Council attracts so little attention in the
modern constitutional literature. It is much less important than it once was,
having been transcended within the domestic constitution by a series of
institutions which might be best understood as outgrowths of it. Its functions
within that domestic constitution are residual, and mostly formal. Even those
few which are of practical significance are carried out in a fashion which is
often considerably less visible, less accessible, than are their analogues in
Parliament. But the Privy Council is not only, and not in the first place, an
institution of the domestic constitution. Rather, it is better understood, both
in the judicial and legislative senses, as representing the beating heart of
what remains of the imperial constitution. Here, its functions are no more
visible, no more accessible – in fact in many cases they are much less so – but
are significantly more important. In relation to some of the OTs, almost all
that there is by way of law derives directly from the operation of the Crown in
Council and only indirectly, if at all, from that of the Crown in Parliament.
Some
of this is not just knowable, but in fact known – though the JCPC's work in
relation to the Commonwealth attracts much more attention than does that in
relation to the OTs – but other elements are mostly closed off, hidden from the
view even of constitutional observers. The Privy Council acts as a
constitutional firewall, keeping the residual empire largely separate from the
domestic constitution of the UK, even where the allegedly distinct institutions
are in substance identical. The result is that the imperial constitution is a
shadow constitution, eclipsed by a domestic constitution whose values it would if
visible work to undermine. It is for this reason that, notwithstanding its
apparent constitutional insignificance, any attempt to remove the Privy Council
from our constitutional order, or to turn its relative formality into absolute
formality by depriving it of all substantive powers, is highly unlikely. To do
so would require the UK to grapple not only with the considerable
constitutional legacy of empire, but also with its ongoing reality.
End of Document