Stanford Journal of International Law
Summer, 1999
35 Stan. J Int'l L. 255
LENGTH:
40519 words
ARTICLE: Reviving the "Public Law Taboo" in
International Conflict of Laws
Philip J. McConnaughay *
* Associate Professor of Law, University of Illinois. Of Counsel,
Morrison & Foerster, San Francisco, California. J.D., University of
Illinois, 1978; B.A., University of Illinois, 1975.
SUMMARY:
... Not long ago, participants in international commercial
transactions could safely assume that conflict of laws principles and
contractual choice of law clauses applied exclusively to private law and did
not operate with respect to public law issues. ... Thus, the public law taboo
in traditional contractual conflict of laws is responsible for three of the four
rules I mentioned at the outset of this Part that ordinarily govern the
question of what law applies to any given international transaction: (1) the
forum will confine its conflict of laws analysis to categories of private law,
thus limiting the forum's possible application of foreign law to private law,
(2) the forum will not apply foreign public law to the transaction, but instead
will dismiss the case if the dispute is governed exclusively by foreign public
law, and (3) the forum will not displace its own applicable public law in favor
of any other law. ... Two questions that might occur concerning the
relationship between the public law taboo and the public policy exception to
conflicts analysis are (1) whether the public law taboo is simply one aspect of
the public policy exception rather than a separate category of law that resides
outside the ambit of conflicts analysis, and (2) whether public policy ever
serves as a reason for permitting the displacement of mandatory forum law in
addition to serving as a reason for barring application of objectionable
foreign law. ...
TEXT:
[*255]
I. Introduction
Not long ago, participants in international commercial
transactions could safely assume that conflict of laws principles n1 and
contractual choice of law clauses applied exclusively to private law and did
not operate with respect to public law issues. If the parties to a transaction
occurring in both Nation A and Nation B became embroiled in a contract dispute
in a court of Nation B, for example, that court might apply Nation A's contract
law as a result of a conflict of laws analysis. The court of Nation B, however,
would not apply Nation A's antitrust, securities, or other "public"
law to the dispute and certainly would not consider the possibility of
displacing its otherwise applicable public law with that of Nation A.
Similarly, if the parties to this transaction had contractually elected the law
of Nation A as the law governing their contract or transaction, a court of
Nation B likely would honor that election by excluding Nation B's own contract
law. However, the court would not interpret the election to include Nation A's
public law or to exclude the application of Nation B's public law. Neither the
selection principles of conflict of laws analysis nor party autonomy to
designate applicable law contractually traditionally influenced or constrained
the jurisdictional reach of a na [*256] tion's public law. A
"public law taboo" existed with respect to both of these principles.
n2
This state of affairs troubled many courts and scholars. The
traditional distinction between public law and private law became more
difficult to maintain as public regulatory legislation encroached increasingly
on areas of conduct and commerce traditionally deemed private and as awareness
grew that even private law (e.g., contracts, torts, property, and family law)
had public significance. One commentator declared the public law/private law
distinction "wholly irrelevant to the organisation of modern society."
n3
Moreover, a belief grew among courts and commentators that, in the
context of international transactions, public law (e.g., antitrust, securities,
exchange controls, general economic regulation) should be subject to
traditional conflict of laws principles. These courts and commentators believed
that concurrent jurisdiction among several nations over the same transaction
unduly burdened international commerce and that rules should be developed to
identify a single national regulatory regime with respect to any given
international issue or transaction. They believed that traditional judicial
inquiries into a nation's power to regulate an international transaction should
be expanded to include an inquiry into the wisdom of applying the regulation.
n4
The traditional separation of public law from conflict of laws
analysis began to give way in the face of these criticisms, and choice of law
principles were increasingly applied to questions concerning the jurisdictional
reach of public law. U.S. courts considering the jurisdictional reach of U.S.
antitrust law to international transactions, for example, began to enlarge
their inquiry to include not only the traditional question of whether the
alleged anticompetitive conduct had occurred in or had effects in the United States,
but also the question of whether, even if U.S. antitrust law applied to the
transaction, jurisdiction nonetheless should be declined because some nation
other than the United States had a greater regulatory interest in the
transaction. n5 Additionally, the Third Restatement of Foreign Relations Law
urged the extension of such interest balancing principles to public laws
generally. n6 U.S. courts even extended to public law the principle that
private parties to international [*257] transactions may
contractually elect applicable law. In a series of decisions culminating just
this year, the U.S. Courts of Appeals for the Second, Fourth, Fifth, Seventh,
Ninth, Tenth, and Eleventh Circuits held that private parties to international
transactions may effectively elect out of otherwise applicable U.S. public law
(in these cases the Securities Acts of 1933 and 1934) so long as the
substituted law "vindicates" similar rights and does "not
subvert" the general policy of the displaced law. n7
This Article contends that these developments have created more
problems for international commerce than they have solved. The task of
identifying, explaining, and weighing the comparative regulatory interests of
different nations in any given international transaction is virtually
impossible for courts and private litigants. Similarly, the assumption that
conflicts rules enhance the predictability of international transactions by
identifying a single national regulatory regime for any given international
transaction or issue seems completely belied by the ex post and inexact nature
of the various interest balancing rules for selecting a single applicable law.
It typically would be far more predictable and less burdensome for an
international transaction to comply with the regulatory regimes of multiple
nations so long as that prospect is known beforehand and accounted for when the
transaction is structured. Although predictability for international commerce
undoubtedly would be enhanced by universally extending to private parties the
ability to elect contractually a single applicable national regulatory law,
that prospect is as inappropriate as it is unlikely insofar as it elevates the
economic interests of private commercial parties over the regulatory interests
of all nations.
Finally, the displacement of forum public law, whether by private
contractual election or comparative interest balancing, carries a substantial
risk of underregulation. Parties to international transactions do not
contractually "opt out" of a given national regulatory scheme or
litigate its applicability because of a desire for more stringent or burdensome
regulation by another nation. When forum public law is displaced, the
likelihood is that it will be replaced by lesser regulation or a regulatory void,
perhaps creating an occurrence of precisely the harm that forum public law was
intended to prevent. n8
This Article argues that these problems suggest that the
traditional public law taboo in conflict of laws should be revived, and that
public law should not be eligible for displacement by contractual election or
choice [*258] of law principles. In fact, the U.S. Supreme Court
has embarked on precisely that path. In Hartford Fire Insurance Co. v.
California, n9 the Court rejected comparative national interest balancing and
considerations of private expectations as possible constraints on the
application of U.S. antitrust law to an international transaction. The Court
recognized that parties to international transactions often must contend with
overlapping, and sometimes inconsistent, regulation by several different
national jurisdictions. Hartford Fire arguably signals a restoration of the
traditional principle that neither conflicts analysis (in Hartford Fire,
"comity") nor principles of contractual autonomy apply to public law,
at least with respect to the possible displacement of forum public law by
foreign law or interests. n10 If correct, this reading indicates a vital and
continuing role for a public law/private law distinction in international conflict
of laws.
Nevertheless, the fact that a public law/private law distinction
remains vital to conflicts analysis does not resolve the definitional problems
that initially led to the collapse of the distinction. The question remains
whether the concepts of public law and private law remain useful for purposes
of distinguishing between those laws and provisions of law that are
appropriately the object of conflicts analysis and those that are not.
Answering that question is the principal objective of this Article.
Part II briefly reviews the traditional separation of public law
from conflict of laws principles and Part III covers the more recent trend of
applying conflicts principles to public law. Part IV explores the serious
problems that result from the merger of those concepts. Part V analyzes the
argument that the Supreme Court's decision in Hartford Fire represents a
resurrection of the traditional public law taboo in conflict of laws. Part VI
then addresses the important question of whether the public law/private law
distinction remains useful for applying the taboo.
The paper concludes in Part VI that, with a single qualification,
the public law/private law distinction does remain useful as a means of
identifying those laws and provisions of law that properly should be subject to
the public law taboo. The qualification is that only mandatory public law
should automatically fall within the taboo; the treatment of nonmandatory
public law should turn on the reasons for its failure to qualify as [*259]
mandatory. All private law, whether mandatory or not, should remain eligible
for choice of law analysis.
These categories of law (or provisions of law) can be identified
according to the two dimensions suggested in the mandatory public law
nomenclature: a private/public dimension and a mandatory/nonmandatory
dimension. The private/public dimension essentially measures the externalities
likely to result from noncompliance with or repeal of the law. The greater the
externalities, the more likely the law should be classified as public (e.g.,
the Sherman Act, the Securities Acts, the Copyright Act); the fewer the
externalities, the more appropriate classification would be as private (e.g.,
laws forbidding covenants not to compete, statutes of fraud). The mandatory/nonmandatory
dimension measures two characteristics: (1) the extent to which the law
restricts private party discretion and regulates private conduct, and (2) the
extent to which the rights and entitlements conferred by the law are not
prospectively waivable. A law that restricts private party discretion and that
is not prospectively waivable is mandatory (e.g., laws forbidding covenants not
to compete, the Sherman Act); a law that does not restrict private party
discretion (e.g., U.C.C. 2) or that is prospectively waivable (e.g., certain
provisions of the U.S. Copyright Act) is not mandatory.
As Part VI.B discusses, "nonmandatory public law" is a
somewhat self-contradictory category insofar as public law is generally
synonymous with "regulatory law" and "regulatory law"
generally refers to legal restrictions on individual discretion that are
mandatory. Nonetheless, a law may both legitimately regulate discretion and be
prospectively waivable. If a law combines those characteristics, that law
should not automatically be deemed mandatory for purposes of the public law
taboo. For example, if the protection of a public law may be waived
prospectively by an individual for whom the protection is intended, it would
make little sense to apply the public law taboo to forbid the contractual
election of different applicable law by that individual if the election meets
whatever requirements attend a prospective waiver. If the protected individual
has not made a contrary contractual election, however, the taboo appropriately
may apply to forbid a choice of law analysis that might displace the particular
public law; the ability to waive prospectively might be so integral to the
particular law's regulatory scheme (e.g., ensuring adequate compensation of a
protected class in exchange for a waiver) that the law is essentially
indistinguishable from a mandatory public law. Conceivably, a prospective
waiver could be so easily obtained that the law should be regarded as
potentially displaceable by ordinary conflicts principles.
Thus, it is possible for public laws to be nonmandatory (e.g.,
certain provisions of the Copyright Act) and for private laws to be mandatory
(e.g., laws forbidding covenants not to compete, statutes of fraud). Only
public laws, however, are eligible for the public law taboo (mandatory public
laws automatically and nonmandatory public laws depending on the reason for
their failure to qualify as mandatory). Private laws never fall within the
taboo, even if mandatory. Mandatory private laws retain [*260]
their mandatory character in a domestic setting only; in a transnational
context, they traditionally become eligible for possible displacement by
contractual election or choice of law analysis. The difference likely reflects
the reduced level of public interest (i.e., likely externalities resulting from
noncompliance or repeal) in private as opposed to public laws. Even if private
laws are mandatory in a domestic setting, the public interest in their
enforcement in an international transaction is insufficient to insist on
application of the law without regard for the expectations of the parties, the
impact on cross-border commerce, and the comparative interests of other
nations.
The discussion in Parts V and VI suggests that these distinctions
explain why the U.S. Supreme Court invoked conflicts principles and comparative
interest balancing in Lauritzen v. Larsen n11 when deciding the jurisdictional
reach of the Jones Act, n12 but expressly rejected consideration of the same
principles in Hartford Fire when deciding the jurisdictional reach of the
Sherman Act. These distinctions also explain why courts are willing to consider
choice of law principles when assessing the applicability to cross-border
transactions of mandatory statutes of frauds and laws forbidding covenants not
to compete, but not when assessing the applicability of mandatory customs,
competition, and health regulations. They suggest, for example, that the U.S.
Supreme Court will not apply choice of law principles when considering the
jurisdictional reach of the U.S. Carriage of Goods by Sea Act, n13 but that it
might when considering the displacement of certain provisions of the U.S.
Copyright Act. n14
Restoring the clear separation of mandatory public law from
conflict of laws principles should benefit both the participants in
international transactions and the nations that host international
transactions. Participants will enjoy greater ex ante certainty with respect to
the identities of the national regulatory regimes with which their transactions
must comply, and thereby be better able either to avoid certain regimes or
account for the cost of compliance by structuring their transactions
accordingly. Nations that host or aspire to host international transactions
will be better able to assess the impact of their mandatory public laws on
international commerce and whether or not the interests served by their
mandatory public laws outweigh the impact. If that assessment implicates the
interests of other nations, any accommodation that is in order can be
negotiated in the political arena rather than imposed unilaterally and without
complete information by the judiciary.
[*261]
II. The Traditional Separation of Public Law from Conflict of Laws
Analysis
The traditional separation of public law from conflict of laws
principles is reflected in four interrelated rules that typically have governed
most courts' consideration of the question of which law or laws apply to any
given international transaction: (1) the forum will confine its conflict of
laws analysis to categories of private law, thus limiting the forum's possible
application of foreign law to private law, (2) the forum will not apply foreign
public law to the transaction, but instead will dismiss the case if the dispute
is governed exclusively by foreign public law, (3) the forum will not displace
applicable forum public law in favor of any other law, and (4) the
applicability of the forum's public law will turn on the intended reach of the
law and not on private contractual election or on whether other nations do or
do not regulate the same transaction. The first three rules are found within
the traditional body of conflicts scholarship and case law; the fourth rule is
found more typically in the body of work concerning the "extraterritorial"
application of a nation's regulatory law. For the purpose of this historical
summary, private law and public law are defined according to the categories or
types of law traditionally within each: private law traditionally includes
contracts, torts, property, and family law, while public law traditionally
includes antitrust, securities, exchange controls, and most economic
regulation. Part VI provides a more detailed elaboration of these definitions.
A. The Limited Scope of Conflicts Analysis
The discipline of conflict of laws is known throughout most of the
world as "the rules of private international law," a name that
intrinsically reflects the understanding that conflicts analysis conventionally
operates with respect to categories of private law but not with respect to
public law. n15 For example, in the absence of a contractual designation of
governing law, a court may identify governing law as the law of the state or
nation with the "most significant relation" to the parties and the
transaction, n16 or the law of the nation to which the contract "is most
closely connected," n17 or the law of the place of the making of the
contract, n18 or [*262] the law of any connected nation that will
validate the contract. n19 The law thus selected by the court as governing law
will include the private law of the designated state or nation (in this
context, essentially the state's or nation's main body of contract law) but not
that state's or nation's public law. The forum's own public law, if applicable,
applies irrespective of the court's conflicts analysis. The same is true in the
event of a contractual designation of governing law: the court will neither
apply the public law of the designated foreign jurisdiction nor decline to
apply applicable, but nondesignated, forum public law. n20
Oddly, this "public law taboo" rarely is explicit in the
articulation of any given theory or approach to contractual choice of law, n21
or in the statutes or rules governing party autonomy to contractually designate
the law applicable to a contract or transaction. n22 However, it clearly serves
as a traditional limitation on each of these means of determining the law
applicable to international commercial transactions and issues. The aspect of
the taboo that forbids forum application of foreign public law appears to have
originated in the centuries old refusal of nations to enforce the penal or
revenue laws of other nations, n23 perhaps in acknowl [*263]
edgment of or deference to their separate sovereignty or spheres of power. n24
If an action appears to be governed exclusively by foreign public law, the
forum will dismiss the case. n25
The aspect of the taboo that forbids the displacement of forum
public law is grounded firmly in the sensible notion that the mandatory regulatory
priorities of the forum should take precedence, when applicable, over the
forum's accommodation of a private party election or foreign law purporting to
displace the forum's mandatory rule. As Professor Batiffol has noted, "If
the proper law of the contract is contrary to some provision of the law of the
forum pertaining to public law, it is [only] natural that the public law should
prevail." n26 Professor Yntema confirmed a general adherence to this
proposition when he reported a pervasive judicial practice of permitting the
parties to international transactions to choose the law that will govern their
transactions, "subject to the general public laws." n27 Traditional
conflicts scholarship assumes [*264] the nondisplacement of forum
public law by party autonomy or contractual conflicts principles. n28 Moreover,
it is explicit in the European Union's Convention on the Law Applicable to
Contractual Obligations. n29
Thus, the public law taboo in traditional contractual conflict of
laws is responsible for three of the four rules I mentioned at the outset of
this Part that ordinarily govern the question of what law applies to any given
international transaction: (1) the forum will confine its conflict of laws
analysis to categories of private law, thus limiting the forum's possible
application of foreign law to private law, (2) the forum will not apply foreign
public law to the transaction, but instead will dismiss the case if the dispute
is governed exclusively by foreign public law, and (3) the forum will not
displace its own applicable public law in favor of any other law.
At this point, it is helpful to consider the relationship between
the public law taboo and the often repeated public policy exception to conflict
of laws analysis. A classic statement of the public policy exception to
conflicts analysis is Justice Cardozo's: A forum properly may refuse to apply
the law designated by conflicts analysis if application of that law "would
violate some fundamental principle of justice, some prevalent conception of
good morals, some deep-rooted tradition of the common [wealth]." n30 The
European Union's Convention on the Law Applicable [*265] to
Contractual Obligations contains a similar limitation by providing that the law
chosen pursuant to the Convention's rules need not be applied if it "is
manifestly incompatible with the public policy of the forum," n31 while
the Restatement (Second) of Conflict of Laws imposes the limitation with
respect to party designated applicable law. n32
Two questions that might occur concerning the relationship between
the public law taboo and the public policy exception to conflicts analysis are
(1) whether the public law taboo is simply one aspect of the public policy
exception rather than a separate category of law that resides outside the ambit
of conflicts analysis, and (2) whether public policy ever serves as a reason
for permitting the displacement of mandatory forum law in addition to serving
as a reason for barring application of objectionable foreign law.
The concept of public policy as an exception to conflicts analysis
is almost unmanageably elastic, and the case law and literature regarding its
scope of application are consequently muddled and ambiguous. n33 Properly
understood, however, the public policy exception applies exclusively to private
law and not at all to public law, and thus is completely distinct from the
public law taboo. The public law taboo demarcates the boundaries of conflicts
analysis; the public policy exception operates within conflicts analysis. The
traditional public law taboo means that, in [*266] any particular
forum, foreign public law is never applied and applicable forum public law is
always applied, irrespective of contractual conflicts analysis or party
designated law. It is not equally true, however, that the foreign private law
designated by conflicts analysis always applies; designated foreign private law
still must survive the forum's public policy. n34 For example, if a court of
State A determines by conflicts analysis or party designation that the law of
State B applies to a particular cross-border transaction or contract, and the
contract law of State B omits a statute of frauds, usury restriction, or
unconscionability doctrine that the law of State A contains (or vice versa), an
issue may arise about whether the public policy of State A nonetheless forbids
the application of State B's law. n35 In contrast, State B's antitrust law or
securities law would not apply because of their status as public laws; State
A's public policy would not need to be invoked to achieve that result. Public
policy sometimes invalidates an otherwise proper contractual choice of law
clause or conflicts analysis, because public law is simply outside the scope of
public policy analysis. n36
With respect to the question of whether public policy ever permits
the displacement of forum public law in addition to barring the application of
objectionable foreign private law, the short answer is "no." At least
until the U.S. Court of Appeals Lloyd's cases permitted the displacement of
otherwise applicable U.S. securities law, n37 no other courts in a contractual
conflicts context invoked domestic public policy as a reason for not applying
domestic public law (one would assume the two synonymous). Public policy traditionally
has been invoked only as a rea [*267] son for barring the
application of objectionable foreign law. n38 As Professor Baade has pointed
out:
Ordre public international [i.e., the public policy exception to
conflicts analysis] serves as the "safety valve' of private international
law by barring the domestic application of an otherwise competent rule of
foreign law to the extent that it conflicts with the public policy of the
forum. It has no application to domestic law, which by definition does not
contradict domestic public policy. n39
It is now appropriate to consider the fourth rule that reflects
the traditional separation of public law from conflict of laws principles: The
applicability of a forum's public law ordinarily turns on the intended scope or
reach of the law and not on whether other nations might regulate (or
purposefully not regulate) the same transaction.
B. The Applicability of Public Law
Conflicts analysis almost by definition seeks to resolve
"conflicts" among competing applicable laws by selecting the single
"most appropriate" law pursuant to a contractual designation by the
parties or pursuant to one of the "comparative interest balancing"
assessments typical of choice of law analysis in the absence of party designation.
n40 This determination is inherently hierarchical, as perhaps it must be in the
context of private contractual relationships when singular guidance is required
to determine the exact nature of the contractual expectation and performance
due between private parties.
Judicial analysis concerning the applicability of public law, in
contrast, traditionally ends where conflicts analysis begins: If the court
determines that the forum's public law applies to the particular transaction or
issue, it does not proceed further to consider the parties' expectations or
some other nation's possible superior interest in the transaction or issue. The
inquiry is not hierarchical: International law contemplates that national
jurisdiction to prescribe law regulating a cross-border transaction will often
be concurrent and overlap and not be mutually exclu [*268] sive.
n41 Thus, the question that traditionally confronts courts considering public
law's applicability to an international transaction is not which nation's
public law should apply, but simply whether the forum's public law applies. As
discussed in the following paragraphs, the answer to that question
traditionally turns on legislative intent and the sufficiency of regulatory
power, not on whether the exercise of that power is otherwise appropriate in
light of other nations' interests. Traditionally, there is no effort (save the
exceptional situation of two or more nations' laws requiring simultaneous
inconsistent conduct n42) to relieve the affected parties of the duty to comply
with the public laws of all of the jurisdictions to which they have submitted.
n43
The seminal case reflecting this traditional approach to the
application of public law is United States v. Aluminum Co. of America, n44 the
famous Alcoa opinion by Judge Learned Hand. n45 The case involved an action by
the U.S. Justice Department seeking to dissolve the Aluminum Company of America
because of its alleged monopolization of the market for alu [*269]
minum ingot in violation of U.S. antitrust law. The relevant portion of Judge
Hand's opinion concerned the application of U.S. antitrust law n46 to a cartel
composed entirely of foreign aluminum companies from Canada, France, Germany,
Switzerland, and Great Britain. The purpose of the cartel was to regulate the
production, price, and trade of aluminum among cartel members. The cartel
organized a separate Swiss corporation, the "Alliance," for that
purpose. n47 There was no evidence that the cartel or any of its members had
performed any acts in furtherance of the cartel in the United States, but there
was substantial evidence that the cartel intended to affect and did affect the
U.S. market for aluminum. n48
Significantly, in deciding whether U.S. antitrust law should apply
to the cartel, Judge Hand expressly rejected the possibility that the laws or
interests of Canada, France, Germany, Switzerland, or Great Britain were
relevant to the court's decision. Instead, he declared the issue to be one
exclusively of U.S. congressional intent:
Did [the cartel] violate 1 of the [Sherman] Act? The answer does
not depend on whether we shall recognize as a source of liability a liability
imposed by another state. On the contrary we are concerned only with whether
Congress chose to attach liability to the conduct outside the United States of
persons not in allegiance to it. That being so, the only question open is
whether Congress intended to impose the liability, and whether our own
Constitution permitted it to do so: as a court of the United States, we cannot
look beyond our own law. n49
Judge Hand acknowledged that Congress presumably intended to abide
by the limits on prescriptive jurisdiction customarily observed by the
community of nations, n50 but he decided that application of U.S. anti
[*270] trust law to the foreign cartel in Alcoa was consistent with
those limitations because the cartel "intended to affect imports and did
affect them," n51 thus falling clearly within the traditional rule of
international law that "any state may impose liabilities, even upon
persons not within its allegiance, for conduct outside its borders that has
consequences within its borders which the state reprehends." n52 The Alcoa
"intended effects" test has remained the touchstone for assessing the
"extraterritorial" reach of prescriptive jurisdiction since. n53
[*271] Obviously, the intended effects test and the
various other traditional bases for justifying an assertion of prescriptive
jurisdiction n54 are not inherently "noncomparative" in the sense
that their application depends on the irrelevance of the interests of other
states to the issue of the jurisdictional reach of public law. For example, the
intended effects test might simply serve as one of several factors for
determining the application of public law, with a hierarchical assessment of
the interests of other nations in the transaction influencing the outcome as
well. n55 But that has not been the case traditionally. Judge Hand's admonition
about courts not "looking beyond our own law" when assessing the
Sherman Act's applicability to an international transaction has accompanied the
intended effects test hand in hand with its transposition to additional areas
of public law. n56
The Second Restatement of Foreign Relations (in contrast to the
Third Restatement, discussed in Part III.A), is decidedly noncomparative in its
approach to prescriptive jurisdiction. It endorses the attachment of legal
consequences to conduct within a state "whether or not such consequences
are determined by the effects of the conduct outside [the state]," n57 and
the attachment of legal consequences to conduct outside the state that causes
effects within the state so long as the prescribed rule "is not
inconsistent with the principles of justice generally recognized by states that
have reasonably developed legal systems." n58 Like the Alcoa intended
effects test, these tests of prescriptive jurisdiction focus on the sufficiency
of the relationship between the conduct or transaction and the prescribing
jurisdiction, not on the strength of that relationship in comparison to other
prescribing jurisdictions. n59
In applying U.S. securities laws to international transactions,
the traditional U.S. approach is similarly indifferent to the regulatory
interests of other nations. n60 U.S. courts have used conduct and intended
effects [*272] tests essentially identical to the Second
Restatement and Alcoa's to determine the reach of the antifraud provisions of
the Securities Exchange Act. n61 The degree of conduct or extent of intended
effects required for the application of U.S. law is the subject of much
litigation and commentary, n62 but the inquiry nonetheless focuses on the
sufficiency of the conduct or effects in an absolute sense, not their
sufficiency in comparison to the relationships to the transaction of other
potentially prescribing jurisdictions. n63 Different tests of
"extraterritorial" application apply to areas of public law other
than antitrust and securities, but they are similarly noncomparative in nature.
n64
[*273] To conclude, a public law taboo traditionally
has applied to conflict of laws to strictly separate issues concerning the
applicability or extraterritorial reach of public law from the conflict of laws
principles ordinarily governing the application of private law to cross-border
transactions. The application of private law to cross-border transactions
usually turns on a private contractual election as to which nation's law shall
apply, or, in the absence of such an election, on a comparative interest
balancing assessment designed to select as applicable the law of the nation
with the most significant relationship to the transaction. The application of
public law to an international transaction traditionally has turned on neither
of these approaches. Public law has applied by virtue of its intent to apply;
neither private party expectations nor other nations' interests have been
relevant to that determination.
III. Abandoning the Public Law Taboo - The Merger of Public Law
and Choice of Law Principles
The public law taboo in conflict of laws became increasingly
difficult to sustain as the traditional distinction between public and private
law increasingly blurred. Regulatory legislation began to invade areas of
commercial life in the traditional domain of private law, n65 and there was an
enormous increase in the codification of all law. n66 Additionally, an
awareness developed that even private law serves governmental purposes and
public interests. n67 Commentators thus came to regard private law as [*274]
something of an "oxymoron" n68 and the public/private law distinction
as an artifact of "simpler times" n69 that is largely
"irrelevant to the organisation of modern society." n70 "The
classical distinction between public and private law, in so far as it affects
transnational activity," wrote Professor Lowenfeld almost two decades ago,
"has long been overtaken - one could well say overwhelmed - by [these]
events." n71
Moreover, there was an emerging belief that issues concerning the
reach or application of public law should be subject in any event to
traditional conflict of laws principles and comparative interest balancing.
Professor Trautman posed the issue as follows: "The question is whether we
are concerned with finding the most appropriate [public] law to govern a
transaction or simply with the sufficiency of the legislative concern of the
United States." n72 Leading scholars answered with resounding support for
"appropriateness," arguing that it is a mistake "to separate the
existence of authority from the wisdom of applying it," n73 and that
"optimal rationality" should govern the determination of applicable
regulatory law rather than simply "minimum contacts" with a
prescribing jurisdiction. n74 These scholars contended that "public
law...[should be] eligible ... for the choice of law process." n75
In addition to the diminishing clarity of the public law/private
law distinction and a preference for rules justified by "wisdom"
rather than simply "power," these commentators advanced two principal
reasons for urging the application of conflicts principles to issues concerning
public law regulation of international transactions: comity among nations and
the facilitation of international commerce.
[*275] With regard to comity, n76 Professor Lowenfeld
argued that Learned Hand's admonition to courts to "not look beyond our
own law" n77 in deciding prescription jurisdiction issues had "an
arrogant, chauvinistic sound." n78 Professor Trautman noted that
"many consider it perverse for the United States to apply its [regulatory]
law ... to foreign activities... in countries whose law tolerates or promotes
what we proscribe," n79 and Professor Brewster objected that, "if
extraterritorial jurisdiction is not confined to the protection of interests
which are not inherently opposed to the interests of other nations, then law,
far from serving its ancient function of providing for an orderly settlement of
dispute, will become an affirmative stimulus to international contention."
n80 These scholars, and others since, have urged courts to consider "the
needs of the international system in determining the territorial scope of
[public law]" n81 and to allocate legislative authority among the
international community so as to achieve a fair and rational distribution of
prescriptive power. n82
Commentators in favor of finding the most appropriate law for a
particular transaction believed that such a proportional allocation of
prescriptive jurisdiction among nations also would help achieve their second
principal goal: the facilitation of international business. "Perhaps the
most important result encouraged by focusing on system needs," wrote
Professor Maier, "is the increased likelihood of developing predictability
in the system." n83 "Predictability" in this sense, of course, refers
to the application of a single rather than multiple public laws to any given
international commercial dispute or issue. The assumption of these commentators
is that concurrent prescriptive jurisdiction affirmatively harms international
business, n84 an assumption perhaps originating with Profes [*276]
sor Beale: "If two laws were present at the same time and in the same
place upon the same subject we should also have a condition of anarchy."
n85 Even if anarchy is not the result of concurrent regulation, these
commentators believe that burdensome overregulation is. n86
These criticisms of the public law taboo soon found expression in
(1) caselaw concerning the application of U.S. antitrust law to international
transactions, (2) sections of the Third Restatement of Foreign Relations
pertaining to prescriptive jurisdiction, (3) considerably more recent caselaw
concerning the application of contractual choice of law clauses (i.e.,
principles of party autonomy) to public law, and (4) caselaw and certain
treaties contemplating forum recognition of foreign public law. The first three
of these developments contemplate the possible displacement of otherwise
applicable forum public law; the fourth contemplates the recognition of foreign
public law, but not necessarily the coincidental displacement of forum public
law. Each of the developments represents the abrogation of the public law taboo
in contractual conflict of laws, and each represents the infusion of conflicts
principles into the standards that traditionally governed the reach and
application of public law.
A. Antitrust Cases
The leading antitrust case abrogating the public law taboo is
Timberlane Lumber Co. v. Bank of America, n87 a case in which, as one
commentator has noted, "conflicts analysis almost entirely replaces [the
traditional public law] inquiry into congressional intent." n88 Timberlane
alleged that Bank of America officials and others "conspired to prevent
Timberlane, throughout its Honduran subsidiaries, from milling lumber in Honduras
and exporting it to the United States [so that] control of the Honduran lumber
export business [could remain] in the hands of a few select individuals
financed and controlled by the Bank." n89 The Ninth Circuit complained
that the district court's assessment of the applicability of U.S. antitrust law
to the alleged conspiracy had focused only on the tradi [*277]
tional Alcoa intended effects test. n90 The Ninth Circuit complained that
"the effects test by itself is incomplete because it fails to consider
other nations' interests," n91 and held that "[a] more comprehensive
inquiry is necessary. We believe that the field of conflict of laws presents
the proper approach." n92 The court then articulated an "interest
balancing" approach n93 to the application of U.S. antitrust law that
explicitly considers, among other factors, the "degree of conflict with
foreign law or policy [and] ... the relative significance of [the] effects on
the United States as compared with those elsewhere." n94
The Third Circuit completely embraced Timberlane's conflicts
approach to antitrust jurisdiction in Mannington Mills, Inc. v. Congoleum Corp.
n95 Mannington alleged that Congoleum unlawfully restrained export trade of
vinyl floor covering by fraudulently securing patents in twenty-six different
foreign nations and then enforcing those patents to prevent Mannington and
others from exporting to those nations. n96 The Third Circuit concluded that
U.S. antitrust law did reach Mannington's claims, n97 but that that question
(i.e., a question of power) was different [*278] from the question
of whether the court should exercise jurisdiction (i.e., a question of wisdom).
n98 The Court then insisted on an "interest balancing" analysis n99
similar to that articulated in Timberlane. n100 The Mannington court insisted
that interest balancing occur with respect to each of the twenty-six nations
involved in Congoleum's alleged conduct. n101 Other courts also expressed some
attraction to an interest balancing approach to the application of U.S.
antitrust law. n102
B. The Restatement (Third) of Foreign Relations Law
Timberlane and Mannington are cited as precedent for section 403
of the Third Restatement of Foreign Relations Law, which addresses limitations
on prescriptive jurisdiction, and which, like Timberlane and Mannington, casts
aside the public law taboo in favor of a multifactor interest balancing
approach to the application of public law to international transactions. n103
The Third Restatement urges that interest balancing be [*279]
considered not merely as a matter of comity, but instead as a requirement of
international law, n104 and that it be undertaken "not only [by]
governments, but also [by] judges." n105
There are three additional ways in which the Third Restatement cements
its effort to abrogate the public law taboo. First, the interest balancing
approach of section 403 of the Third Restatement applies to the judicial
evaluation of whether prescriptive jurisdiction exists ab initio for any given
application of public law n106; it is not limited, as was its predecessor,
section 40 of the Second Restatement, to suggesting interest balancing only in
the event that applicable public laws of two different nations "require
inconsistent conduct on the part of a person." n107 Con [*280]
sequently, under the Third Restatement, concurrent public law jurisdiction, to
the extent that it would continue at all, would be the exception rather than
the rule. n108 Second, section 403 of the Third Restatement requires interest
balancing with respect to the application of any public law to an international
transaction, not just antitrust law, as in Timberlane and Mannington. n109 And
finally, section 403 of the Third Restatement suggests that prescriptive
jurisdiction should be limited not only by the interests of other nations in
comparison to those of the prescribing nation, but also by the expectation
interests of private parties. n110 In this respect, section 403 anticipates the
next major abrogation of the public law taboo: the inclusion of public law
within the conflicts doctrine permitting the private contractual displacement
of otherwise applicable law.
C. The Contractual Displacement of Otherwise Applicable Public Law
In perhaps the most remarkable abrogation of the public law taboo,
seven U.S. Circuit Courts of Appeals, in decisions culminating just this year,
n111 have permitted parties to international commercial transactions to
contractually opt out of otherwise applicable public law (the Securities Acts
of 1933 and 1934 in all of the cases), so long as the law they substitute for
the displaced public law "vindicates" similar rights and does
"not subvert" the general policy of the displaced law. All of the
cases involved essentially identical international transactions: investments by
U.S. investors in the Lloyd's of London insurance market.
The Lloyd's insurance market consists of over 300 syndicates which
compete for underwriting business. Investors in each syndicate are known as
"Names." Names are solicited from countries other than England, but
all prospective Names must travel to London to participate in a
[*281] personal interview during which their financial commitment
is explained and all final agreements are concluded. The agreements include
choice of law clauses designating the law of England as the governing law, and
choice of forum clauses requiring any disputes relating to the agreements to be
resolved in England. The agreements specify that each Name is liable for
underwriting losses only to the extent of the individual Name's interest in the
particular syndicate, but each Name's personal liability is unlimited with
respect to that interest. n112
During the late 1980s and early 1990s, several Lloyd's
underwriting syndicates experienced substantial unanticipated losses as a
result of asbestosis and pollution claims, the bombing of Pan Am Flight 103
over Lockerbee, Scotland, and the devastation in Florida caused by Hurricane
Hugo. Lloyd's estimated that its losses during these years would exceed
premiums by $ 22 billion. n113 Pursuant to the agreements the Names had signed,
individual Names of the syndicates that had insured these losses were
personally liable for the $ 22 billion excess in proportion to their interest
in each syndicate, a prospect that could mean financial ruin for many Names.
The American Names who were exposed to these losses sought relief
in U.S. courts under U.S. securities laws, alleging that they had been
fraudulently induced to invest in the riskiest Lloyd's syndicates and that
Lloyd's had failed to disclose material facts and risk factors concerning their
investments. n114 The Names argued, essentially on the basis of the traditional
public law taboo, that the choice of law and choice of forum clauses in their
contracts with Lloyd's did not bar their Securities Acts complaints in U.S.
courts. n115
Because the Supreme Court already had held by the time of the
Lloyd's cases that claims under the U.S. Securities Acts are arbitrable, n116
[*282] the change of forum issue alone was largely inconsequential
to the outcome of the Lloyd's cases. n117 The heart of the Lloyd's courts'
analyses focused on the displacement of U.S. securities law that would result
from enforcement of the choice of law clauses to which the Names had agreed.
Significantly, all of the Lloyd's courts relied exclusively on
Supreme Court precedent from the private law context - specifically, contract
and tort claims arising in international maritime transactions n118 - for a
decisional rule that choice of law and forum clauses in international
transactions generally are enforceable so long as they are
"reasonable," i.e., so long as the chosen law neither deprives the
plaintiffs of a remedy nor contravenes a strong U.S. public policy. n119 The
Lloyd's courts declined to decide the jurisdictional issues concerning the
applicability of U.S. securities law to the Names' investments, n120 assuming
instead that even if U.S. securities law applied to the investments, U.S.
public law was just as displaceable as private law by a valid choice of law
clause. The Lloyd's courts then proceeded to assess the reasonableness of the
choice clauses at issue according to factors strikingly similar to those
suggested by Section 403 of the Third Restatement of Foreign Relations Law
n121: the existence [*283] of justified expectations as reflected
in the clauses, n122 the relative adequacy of English remedies and procedures
for vindicating the Names' claims, n123 and the comparatively greater interest
of England in regulating the Names' investments in Lloyd's. n124 The Lloyd's
courts concluded on the basis of this comparative interest balancing analysis
that the choice clauses were enforceable despite their displacement of
otherwise applicable U.S. securities law.
In combination with Timberlane and Mannington and section 403 of
the Third Restatement of Foreign Relations law, the Lloyd's cases would appear
to abrogate entirely that prong of the traditional public law taboo forbidding
the displacement of otherwise applicable forum public law. That leaves for
consideration the remaining prong of the taboo: the recognition by a forum of
foreign public law.
D. The Recognition of Foreign Public Law
As discussed in Part IV of this Article, the recognition of
foreign public law claims by another nation's tribunal stands on entirely
different footing from the displacement of forum public law. The recognition of
foreign public law claims, for example, need not displace forum public law; nor
must the applicability of foreign public law turn on a judicial interest
balancing assessment rather than a determination of the law's intent to apply.
Similarly, the recognition of foreign public law tends to advance governmental
and regulatory interests; the displacement of fo [*284] rum public
law tends to defeat them. And there are other differences as well.
The purpose of this brief Subpart, however, is not to evaluate the
erosion of this prong of the public law taboo, but only to document its
occurrence. The most prominent example is Article 7(1) of the European Union
Convention on the Law Applicable to Contractual Obligations, which provides
that effect "may" be given "to the mandatory rules of the law of
another country with which the situation has a close connection, if ... under
the law of [that] country, those rules must be applied whatever the law
applicable to the contract." n125 Switzerland's contractual conflict of
laws rule is similar: "The application of a provision of foreign law is
not excluded solely because public-law character is attributed to it." n126
Section 187 of the Second Restatement of Conflicts also would seem to support
occasional recognition of foreign public law, n127 to the extent, of course,
the Restatement of Conflicts even applies to public law. n128
There also is some tendency at the judicial level in various
nations to recognize and apply certain foreign public law claims (particularly
if the foreign public law claim is analogous to private law). n129 One can
argue on the basis of the Supreme Court's consistent rulings permitting the foreign
arbitration of U.S. public law claims, n130 which are predicated on the assumed
importance to international commerce of permitting foreign forums to hear U.S.
public law claims, n131 that the Supreme Court would encourage reciprocity in
this regard by U.S. courts. n132
IV. The Problems With Merger - Virtues of the Public Law Taboo
Three overarching problems arise from the judicial application of
conflicts principles to issues concerning the applicability of public law. The
first is underregulation. The risk of diminished regulation is great whenever
private contractual election or comparative interest balancing analysis
displaces forum public law. Parties to international transactions do not
contractually "opt out" of a given national regulatory scheme or
[*285] litigate its inapplicability because of a desire for more
stringent or burdensome regulation by another nation. The displacement of
otherwise applicable public law might in some ways promote private
international transactions, but clearly does so at the expense of laws designed
to ensure the integrity of such transactions.
The second problem is that courts and private parties are
completely ill equipped to undertake the complex presentational and decisional
burdens of attempting to identify and balance the interests of multiple nations
in order to achieve a fair and equitable allocation of prescriptive
jurisdiction (if, in fact, such an allocation even is achievable). That process
belongs in the political arena. It is no surprise that the parties in
Mannington Mills settled rather than undertake the task assigned by the Court
of Appeals. That task involved weighing the interests of the United States in
the enforcement of its antitrust laws against the interests of each of the
twenty-six possibly affected nations in administering their patent laws
independently of U.S. interference. n133
The final overarching problem of applying conflicts principles to
public law is that their merger substantially reduces predictability in
international transactions rather than increasing it. It is a specious notion
that the ex post interest balancing determination of a single applicable public
law lends greater predictability to international transactions than ex ante
certainty that, if the transaction exceeds some threshold of contacts with a
particular jurisdiction, that jurisdiction's public law will apply to the
transaction. Only in the latter instance can applicable public law properly be
factored in and accounted for in structuring the transaction. The
"value" of ex post interest balancing resides exclusively in the
litigation arsenal for tactical use if the transaction falls apart.
This Part of the Article briefly elaborates on each of these
problems, and then concludes with a short discussion of whether the problems
are as serious with respect to the recognition of foreign public law as they
are with respect to the displacement of forum public law.
A. The Problem of Underregulation
There is a growing body of scholarship documenting the risk of underregulation
that flows so logically and naturally from the displacement of forum public
law. n134 No "reasonably parallel law," as Professor Weinberg has
noted, necessarily or even probably "springs into place" following
displacement. n135 Different nations often have vastly different regulatory
objectives and needs and, as international commerce expands to include less
developed nations, vastly different capacities to promulgate and enforce
regulations. It seems far more probable that lesser [*286] regulation
or a regulatory void springs into place following the displacement of forum
public law than it does that parallel or greater regulation will occur. Thus,
displacement often will allow precisely the harm that forum public law was
intended to prevent. n136 There is no more likely an explanation of a
defendant's opposition to forum public law in the first place. n137
Additionally, it is by no means clear why a nation with
legislative competence to regulate commercial conduct of concern to it should yield
regulatory authority to another nation with a closer relationship to or
interest in the transaction, but perhaps with less regulatory interest or
capacity. Apart from conclusory claims of "comity" n138 and
undocumented assertions that singular regulation necessarily promotes
international commerce while multiple regulation necessarily harms it, n139 one
searches the conflicts literature in vain for actual illustrations of either
the rationale behind or consequences of such a subordination of national interest.
In fact, by deferring regulatory responsibility to another nation, the
displacing forum would seem to be depriving itself of precisely the data
necessary to make an informed judgment about whether considerations of comity
or international commerce outweigh the need for the displaced public
regulation.
[*287] The same point is true, except perhaps with
even more force, with respect to the private contractual displacement of forum
public law, as in the Lloyd's cases. Ordinarily when private commercial parties
seek to avoid the public regulation of a particular nation, they conduct their
activities so as not to exceed that nation's prescriptive jurisdictional
threshold. If a court instead grants them the right to contractually avoid that
nation's public regulation despite their engaging in conduct or producing
effects sufficient to come within that nation's prescriptive jurisdiction, the
court essentially deprives that nation of the information necessary to test the
assumption on which the exemption is made - namely, that the value of the
regulation is outweighed by the possible loss of international commercial
transactions and/or gains in international comity. Moreover, it is not clear
why the parties' mere contractual announcement of their desire to avoid that
nation's public law should result in the subordination of the nation's right to
regulate the conduct of the parties. It is as if the Lloyd's courts have placed
in the hands of private parties the long discredited "liberty of contract"
sword used by the Supreme Court during the early twentieth century to strike
down social welfare and economic regulatory legislation as an undue
interference with the private right of contract. n140 The displacement of forum
public law in deference to a contractual choice of law clause says little or
nothing about international commerce or comity. It says much, however, about a
particular court's preference for private over public interests.
B. The Institutional Competence Issue
In Laker Airways Ltd. v. Sabena, Belgian World Airlines, n141 a
U.S. antitrust action by the low cost British air carrier against a group of
foreign and domestic U.S. air carriers for allegedly conspiring to put Laker
out of business through predatory pricing, the D.C. Circuit expressly rejected
the Timberlane and Mannington "interest balancing" approach to the
jurisdictional reach of U.S. antitrust law, and in doing so, addressed the
issue of a court's institutional competence to engage in interest balancing:
An English or American court cannot refuse to enforce a law its
political branches have already determined is desireable and necessary.... The
desireability of applying ambiguous legislation to a particular transaction may
imply the presence or absence of legislative intent. However, once a decision
is made that the political branches intended to rely on a legitimate base of
prescriptive jurisdiction to regulate activities affecting foreign commerce
within [*288] the domestic forum, the desireability of the law is no
longer an issue for the courts. n142
Even the proponents of public law "interest balancing"
acknowledge that "it may be difficult for a court to find statutory
authority for this kind of selective application of a regulatory statute."
n143
Another problem with judicial interest balancing, as the
settlement on remand of the Mannington Mills v. Congoleum Corp. perhaps
revealed, n144 is that courts and private litigants typically are ill equipped
to undertake the sometimes enormous presentational and decisional burdens that
accompany interest balancing. As the Laker Airways court noted, "we
seriously doubt whether we could adequately chart the competing problems and
priorities that inevitably define the scope of any nation's interest in a
legislated remedy." n145
Finally, interest balancing by courts necessarily portends
negative consequences for efforts by the political or executive departments of
government to negotiate transnational allocations of jurisdiction or
harmonizations of law, and possibly to otherwise conduct foreign affairs. As
Professor Weintraub noted:
In the long term, reasonable enforcement of our antitrust and
securities laws under the effects doctrine [without interest balancing],
despite friction with foreign countries, is [more] likely to lead to
international cooperation and bilateral agreements of cooperation.... If in
fact a significant sacrifice of United States interests results from attempts
to serve comity, international accommodation may again, ironically, be retarded
rather than ad [*289] vanced. Our bargaining chips will have been
given away before the political branches could use them. n146
C. The Problem of Predictability
If multifactor balancing tests for determining applicable public
law "defy predictable application" by courts, n147 they clearly are
useless as planning tools for the participants in international transactions.
Interest balancing is inherently backward looking; it is invoked only as a
defense to the application in litigation of a particular public law, and the
only predictable consequence for international commerce is a significant
escalation of litigation risks and costs.
Parties to international transactions ordinarily conduct their
activities with the understanding that they will be subject to the public
regulatory laws of those nations in which they engage in conduct or in which
their conduct causes substantial effects. They might have different opinions
about the level or threshold of conduct or effects they must surpass before
their transaction becomes subject to a given nation's public law. However, they
never assume that, despite surpassing that level or threshold, they nonetheless
can escape that nation's public law because some other nation's relation to the
transaction is "more significant" than the first's. Common sense
alone dictates this strategy as the only prudent approach to multinational
business planning and conduct; it necessarily is the understanding on which
international transactions are negotiated. Upsetting this expectation in favor
of ex post interest balancing does not favor international commerce as interest
balancing proponents contend. Rather, it favors international defendants.
Interest balancing does far more to defeat private expectations than it does to
serve them.
As unattractive an intellectual exercise as it may be for many
judges and scholars, counting the contacts of conduct and effects between an
international transaction and potential prescribing jurisdictions is a far more
predictable planning tool for international business (even if the result is
multiple, concurrent regulation of any given international transaction) than
any ex post "interest balancing" assessment designed to identify only
a single regulatory jurisdiction. n148 To quote Judge Posner from a domestic
conflicts context, "the opponents of mechanical rules of
[*290] conflict of laws ... have given too little weight to the
virtues of simplicity." n149
D. The Recognition of Foreign Public Law
Professor Lowenfeld's groundbreaking work to abolish the "public
law taboo" was predicated as much on arguments in favor of recognizing
foreign public law as it was on the occasional need to displace otherwise
applicable forum public law. n150 My foregoing criticisms of abolishing the
public law taboo apply much more forcefully to the latter prong of the taboo
than they do to the former. In fact, recognizing foreign public law - at least
when it occurs without the coincidental displacement of forum public law -
serves many of the same policies that are undermined by the displacement of
forum public law.
For example, the recognition of foreign public law tends to
advance the goals and purposes of economic regulation, while the displacement
of forum public law tends to diminish them. n151 Although there obviously could
be a significant diminution in the substantive protections of foreign public
law if the substitute forum's procedures fail to provide a level of fairness
and accuracy similar to that which is available in the law supplying forum,
n152 overall one would expect a pro-regulatory effect from the judicial
recognition and application of foreign public law, particularly when the
defendant or the defendant's assets are unavailable for claim in the foreign
nation that supplies the applicable public law. n153
Similarly, the decision to recognize and apply applicable foreign
public law is far more consistent with the traditional role of courts and
traditional judicial decisionmaking than is the decision to displace otherwise
applicable forum public law. The former decision focuses on the law's intent to
apply, and the latter on reasons not to apply the law despite its intent to
apply. The recognition of foreign public law need not concern "interest
balancing" as opposed to the more universal "conduct or intended effects"
test of prescriptive jurisdiction, and it need never involve the displacement
of otherwise applicable forum public law. Thus, the judicial recognition of
foreign public law also need not create the problems of predictability for
international commerce that plague the dis [*291] placement of
forum public law as a result of ex post interest balancing. In fact, the
recognition of foreign public law might even enhance the predictability of
international transactions by reducing the possibility of forum shopping.
Although it may be true that courts will be less adept at applying (and
discerning the underlying policies of) foreign public law than they are at
applying forum public law, the decisionmaking process and parameters involved
in each likely will be similar.
Thus, the problems that plague the merger of conflicts principles
with public law do not apply nearly as forcefully with respect to the
recognition of foreign public law as they do with respect to the displacement
of forum public law.
V. Reviving the "Public Law Taboo" - Hartford Fire
Insurance v. California
Inasmuch as Timberlane, Mannington Mills, section 403 of the Third
Restatement of Foreign Relations Law, and the Lloyd's cases represent the
abrogation of the public law taboo, Hartford Fire n154 represents its revival -
at least with respect to that prong of the taboo forbidding the displacement of
forum public law by contractual election or choice of law principles. Perhaps
that seems a surprising assertion about an opinion that never so much as
mentions "public law" and whose holding is not unambiguous. But
Hartford Fire clearly reads like a specific application of the public law taboo
insofar as it suggests very plainly that notions of "comity" and
comparative interest balancing are not permissible constraints on the
jurisdictional reach of the Sherman Act, n155 except possibly in the most
extraordinary situation of a "true" conflict of laws that imposes
impossibly inconsistent obligations on the affected parties. And I believe the
broader proposition emerges not so much from what the Hartford Fire majority
says in its opinion, but from what it does not say about the dissent's
assertion that the majority had failed to follow the Court's previous decisions
in Lauritzen v. Larsen n156 and Romero v. International Termi
[*292] nal Operating Co., n157 both of which applied notions of
comity and comparative interest balancing to the question of the jurisdictional
reach of a federal statute, the Jones Act, n158 to international transactions.
The public law taboo explains both the Court's refusal to apply a conflicts
analysis in Hartford Fire and the Court's application of a conflicts analysis
in Lauritzen and Romero: the Sherman Act is within the taboo, while the Jones
Act is not.
Hartford Fire involved lawsuits by nineteen states and a number of
private plaintiffs alleging that certain U.S. primary insurers and certain
London reinsurers had conspired in violation of the Sherman Act to limit or
eliminate several types of pollution insurance coverage in the United States.
n159 The majority treated the London defendants as having conceded that the
jurisdictional reach of the Sherman Act was sufficient to apply to their
alleged conspiracy, n160 thus effectively leaving for Supreme Court resolution
only the question of whether considerations of international comity should
constrain the exercise of that jurisdiction. n161 The Court then technically
dodged that issue as well by declaring it inappropriate for a court even to
consider matters of comity in the absence [*293] of a "true
conflict between domestic and foreign law." n162 The Court defined a
"true conflict" in the negative by explaining that "no conflict
exists ... "where a person subject to regulation by two states can comply
with the laws of both,'" n163 and then determined that no conflict was
present in Hartford Fire "since the London reinsurers do not argue that
British law requires them to act in some fashion prohibited by the law of the
United States ... or claim that their compliance with the laws of both
countries is otherwise impossible." n164
A. The Demise of Timberlane, Mannington Mills and Section 403.
Although the Hartford Fire majority opinion seems incredibly
stingy in not stating explicitly and unequivocally that a court should not
consider the interests of other nations when considering the applicability, ab
initio, of the Sherman Act to an international transaction, that is precisely
the message that results from the "true conflict" requirement, n165
and that is exactly how the Hartford Fire dissent reads the majority opinion.
n166 Thus, it seems beyond reasonable dispute that the comparative interest
analysis tests of prescriptive jurisdiction mandated by Timberlane and
Mannington Mills n167 do not survive Hartford Fire. n168
Nor should section 403 of the Third Restatement of Foreign
Relations Law's proposed judicial comparative interest balancing with respect
to prescriptive jurisdiction regardless of whether a "true conflict"
of laws exists survive Hartford Fire. n169 Recall that one of the principal
changes instituted by section 403 of the Third Restatement to the approach to
prescriptive jurisdiction of its predecessor, section 40 of the Second
Restatement, n170 was to insist on judicial comparative interest balancing in
answering the question of whether prescriptive jurisdiction exists ab initio,
n171 rather than to restrict comparative interest balancing to cases in which
the laws of two states "require inconsistent conduct upon the part of a
person." Hartford Fire now makes clear without doubt that an assertion of
prescriptive jurisdiction that meets the Alcoa "intended effects"
test is reasonable and that any judicial comparative interest balancing in
those circumstances is inappropriate. n172 Hartford Fire thus seems to read
section 403(2) out of the Third Restatement for purposes of judicial de
[*294] terminations of ab initio prescriptive jurisdiction.
Moreover, the identification of Hartford Fire's "true conflict"
requirement with section 40's "require inconsistent conduct" standard
suggests that a consequence of Hartford Fire will be effectively to restore
section 40 as the rule of decision in cases of true prescriptive conflict. n173
The Hartford Fire dissent essentially believed that the only task
confronting the Supreme Court was to engage in comparative interest balancing
in order to determine whether the obviously substantial interest of Great
Britain in regulating the London reinsurers should outweigh application of the
Sherman Act to their conduct in that case. n174 The dissent believed that the
differing interests of the United States and Great Britain in regulating the
London reinsurers was conflict enough for conducting a comparative interest
analysis. It rejected the majority's "true conflict" requirement as
producing conflict. n175 In essence, the dissent treated the issue of the
Sherman Act's applicability exactly as if it presented a standard question of
conflict of laws, and insisted that the Supreme Court's prior decisions in
Lauritzen v. Larsen n176 and Romero v. International Terminal Operating Co.
n177 dictated precisely that approach. n178 The Hartford Fire majority did not
so much as mention either Lauritzen or Romero.
In fact, both Lauritzen and Romero did apply a standard conflict
of laws, comparative interest balancing approach to questions regarding the
jurisdictional reach of the Jones Act. Both cases concerned the applicability
of the Jones Act to personal injury claims by foreign seamen while aboard
foreign registered vessels sailing under foreign flags. n179 There was some
nexus in each case between the injured seaman and the United States - in
Lauritzen the employment contact was made in New York, and in Romero the injury
occurred in U.S. waters - but there was also a significant nexus among the
seamen, their vessels, and one or more other nations. n180
[*295] The Supreme Court made abundantly clear in both
Lauritzen and Romero that the issue of the Jones Act's applicability to the
injured seamen's claims turned on standard conflict of laws principles and
comparative interest balancing. In Lauritzen the Court explained the approach
as follows:
International or maritime law in such matters as this does not
seek uniformity and does not purport to restrict any nation from making and
altering its laws to govern its own shipping and territory. However, it aims at
stability ... through ... considerations of comity.... Maritime law, like our
municipal law, has attempted to avoid or resolve conflicts between competing
laws by ascertaining and valuing points of contact between the transaction and
the states or governments whose competing laws are involved. The criteria ...
[are] arrived at from weighing of the significance of one or more connecting
factors between the... transaction regulated and the national interest served
by the assertion of authority. n181
The Romero Court emphasized that:
We must apply those principles of choice of law that are consonant
with the needs of a general federal maritime law and with due recognition of
our self-regarding respect for the relevant interests of foreign nations in the
regulation of maritime commerce .... The controlling considerations are the
interacting interests of the United States and of foreign countries, and in
assessing them we must move with the circumspection appropriate when this Court
is adjudicating issues inevitably entangled with the conduct of our
international relations. n182
In both Lauritzen and Romero comparative interest balancing caused
the Supreme Court to refrain from applying the Jones Act. n183
The Hartford Fire dissent assumed that, because Lauritzen and
Romero had both insisted on the judicial application of comparative interest
balancing in determining the international jurisdictional reach of a federal statute,
those decisions necessarily controlled resolution of the same issue with
respect to the Sherman Act. n184 In fact, that is precisely the assumption made
about Lauritzen and Romero by the early proponents of merging conflicts
principles and public law: "Two recent decisions... suggest that statutory
interpretation may appropriately merge with conflict-of-laws thinking."
n185
[*296] The assumption, however, is flawed, and both
the flaw and the Hartford Fire majority's silence about Lauritzen and Romero is
explained by the public law taboo. Part VI of this Article, concerning the
definition of "public law," explains that the statutory forms the
Jones Act and the Sherman Act take do not automatically make them both
"public laws," even in the most traditional sense. n186 Rather, the
Jones Act is but the statutory vehicle for the assertion of a common law tort,
n187 and common law torts comprise a traditional category of private law that
has long been subject to conflict of laws analysis. n188 The opposite is true
of the Sherman Act, perhaps the preeminent example of traditionally recognized
"public law." n189 To ignore that fundamental distinction, as did the
Hartford Fire dissent, is to merge conflict of laws and public law; to honor
the distinction, as did the Hartford Fire majority in their silence about
Lauritzen and Romero, is to honor the public law taboo and the separation of
public law and conflict of laws. n190 It is for this very reason that Hartford
Fire signals a revival of the public law taboo. n191
[*297] Before addressing the important remaining
question of how one goes about identifying the public laws that are subject to
the public law taboo in today's codified world, n192 I shall briefly consider
the implications of Hartford Fire on the holdings of the Lloyd's cases: that
forum public law may be displaced by a contractual choice of law clause.
B. The Impending Demise of the Lloyd's Cases
I believe that Hartford Fire's revival of the public law taboo
compels the conclusion that private contractual choice of law clauses are no
more permissible a constraint on the congressionally intended reach of public
law than are the regulatory interests of foreign nations. In fact, the Lloyd's
courts appeared to do little more in those cases than use contractual choice of
law clauses as vehicles for conducting precisely the comparative interest
balancing analysis forbidden by Hartford Fire. n193
The similarities between Hartford Fire and the Lloyd's cases are
striking. Both concerned conduct or the effect of conduct in the United States
by British insurers subject in Great Britain to a comprehensive regulatory
scheme governing the British insurance industry. n194 Both concerned conduct by
the British insurers that presumably was perfectly legal under (but not
mandated by) the British regulatory scheme, but allegedly illegal under U.S.
public law. n195 Additionally, the applicability of U.S. public law to the
transactions in both Hartford Fire and the Lloyd's cases was either conceded or
assumed. n196 Thus, the only real issue in both was whether factors other than
Congressional intent were of sufficient weight to constrain the exercise of
U.S. jurisdiction. Finally, both Hartford Fire and the Lloyd's cases involved
transactions in which the comparative weight of the respective U.S. and British
regulatory interests seemed to favor Great Britain. n197 The Hartford Fire
Court held that U.S. [*298] public law applied in these
circumstances; the Lloyd's courts held that it did not.
There were only two salient differences between Hartford Fire and
the Lloyd's cases. First, Hartford Fire involved the jurisdictional reach of
the Sherman Act, whereas the Lloyd's cases involved the jurisdictional reach of
the Securities Acts. Second, Hartford Fire did not involve a contractual choice
of law clause designating British law as applicable law, whereas the Lloyd's
cases did.
Insofar as both the Hartford Fire and Lloyd's courts either
determined or assumed that Congress intended the U.S. antitrust or securities
laws to apply to the respective transactions in those cases, one would expect
the different outcomes in the cases, as well as the two principal differences
between the cases, to be explained by the prospective waivability of rights
secured by the securities laws, with the consequence of prospective waivability
being that otherwise applicable U.S. securities laws could be displaced by the
contractual designation of some other nation's law. But that explanation fails
as the Securities Acts include explicit antiwaiver provisions. n198 Thus, apart
from their differences in subject matter, the mandatory nature of the U.S.
antitrust and securities laws seems indistinguishable.
In fact, the Lloyd's courts presumably would agree with that
proposition because none of them found that rights secured by the Securities
Acts had been prospectively waived. Indeed, the opposite is true. The Lloyd's
courts found that the plaintiffs in those cases effectively had not waived
their rights under the Securities Acts, despite the contractual displacement of
the Securities Acts as applicable law, because the remedies available to the
plaintiffs under British law were consistent with the remedies available under
displaced U.S. securities law. n199 In other words, the Lloyd's courts determined
that there was no significant conflict between U.S. and British law with
respect to regulation of the securities fraud at issue in those cases, and thus
that the displacement of otherwise applicable U.S. securities law was
unobjectionable.
The lesson of Hartford Fire, of course, is that the absence of a
true conflict with foreign law actually compels the assertion of applicable
U.S. regulatory jurisdiction. Only in a "true conflict" would it be
permissible [*299] for a court to consider the displacement of
otherwise applicable public law as a result of comparative interest balancing.
Yet, comparative interest balancing is exactly the analysis undertaken by the
Lloyd's courts by way of the contractual choice of law clauses in those cases.
None of the Lloyd's courts suggested that the contractual expectations of
private parties on their own accord should be sufficient to displace otherwise
applicable public law. Instead, they all relied on Great Britain's
comparatively greater regulatory interest in the transactions. n200
Consequently, the principles espoused by the Lloyd's courts should not survive
Hartford Fire. n201
Thus, Hartford Fire suggests that the public law taboo is as alive
and well with respect to the scope of contractual choice of law clauses as it
is with respect to the scope of conflicts analysis in the absence of
contractual choice. The taboo's revival will reduce the threat of
underregulation of transnational commercial activity, n202 enhance the ex ante
predictability of applicable law issues for participants in international
transactions, n203 and restore judicial conflicts analysis to its appropriate
domain, n204 provided, of course, that the public law within the public law
[*300] taboo can be distinguished reliably from those private and
possibly public laws and provisions of law residing outside the taboo. The
final Part of this Article addresses this topic.
VI. What is "Public Law" Anyway?
The resurrection of the public law taboo does not eliminate the
definitional problem that was partly responsible for its earlier demise. n205
The codification of private law and the intrusion of public law into areas
traditionally deemed private has obscured the traditional public law/private
law distinction that once gave clear meaning to the public law taboo. The
question is whether that distinction remains viable, or whether instead, as
several commentators contend, the public law/private law dichotomy has lost
"its utility" n206 to the point of being "meaningless" n207
and "too blunt an instrument for the present day." n208
Before examining that question, it is important to keep in mind
the distinction the public law taboo is seeking to express: Contractual
election or choice of law analysis may displace some national laws but they may
not displace others. Nondisplaceable laws should apply as a perquisite of
national sovereignty to prescribe law within the general limitations
traditionally imposed by international law. n209 The national interest in
enforcing these laws virtually by definition outweighs private contractual
interests and even a comparatively greater interest of some other nation in
regulating an international transaction to which such a law applies. The
important question is how courts and lawyers can identify these national laws
that are beyond the scope of contractual autonomy and conflicts analysis, not
what such laws should be called.
A. Some Traditional Definitions of Private Law and Public Law
One disadvantage of the public law/private law nomenclature is
that it does not have a clear history or context in common law jurisdic
[*301] tions. n210 A public/private distinction for most U.S.
lawyers and legal scholars is evocative of the difference between matters
appropriate for government attention or regulation and matters that are outside
the bounds of legitimate government concern. n211 Adding the word
"law" to the "private" side of that distinction would be a
contradiction in terms; in that sense, all law is public. n212
But the fact that all law serves to order relationships - in
contrast to the completely autonomous ordering that occurs in the "private
sphere" - does not mean that all of the relationships ordered by law are
equally "public." And it is in that sense, perhaps, that a public law/private
law dichotomy begins to make some sense.
In modern Roman law, explained Roscoe Pound, "private law had
to do with adjusting the relations and securing the interests of individuals
and determining the controversies between man and man, while public law had to
do with the frame of government, the functions of public officials, and
adjustment of relations between individuals and the state." n213 Professor
Merryman explained that "private law was that area of the law in which the
sole function of government was the recognition and enforcement of private
rights," n214 and as Professor Maier has noted, when "courts are ...
considering the rights and duties of private parties to each other ... the
interests of governments are not directly engaged." n215 In contrast,
"[a] government always has a direct interest in the outcome of a [public
law] case, even when the governmental viewpoint is represented by a
citizen-prosecutor seeking private recovery." n216 The "driving
consideration" in public law matters, consequently, is "the
effectuation of the public interest." n217 Public law concerns public
harm, [*302] private law, private harm. n218 These characteristics
have led many to equate public law with statutes. n219
Thus far, of course, these traditional definitions of public law
and private law are not particularly helpful in addressing the definitional
problems that led to the collapse of the distinction. Equating public law with
statutes hardly illuminates the distinction in an era of codification. n220 The
private interest/public interest, private harm/public harm continuums are
problematic as well. Many economists view much of the
"anticompetitive" activity regulated by antitrust laws as inflicting
essentially private harms, n221 and there seems to be a continually growing
body of law and economics literature finding that traditional private law
categories such as contracts, torts and property serve the public interest in
efficiency n222 and otherwise express public regulatory, deterrent and
declaratory policies. n223
But the fact that much private law has a public dimension and some
public law has a private dimension does not necessarily make all law equally
public in a way that undermines the utility of the public law taboo. Clearly
there is a difference in degree between the public harm that results from an
interpersonal tort or failed contractual transaction and the public harm that
results from price fixing in the market for a popular commodity or from
misleading statements in financial disclosures about publicly held companies.
As discussed below, perhaps that degree of difference can be expressed in a way
that continues to make a private law/public law dichotomy useful for purposes
of honoring the public law taboo.
First, though, there is another traditional dimension of public
law that I have not yet discussed - its regulatory and mandatory nature. It is
precisely because of public law's focus on the public interest and preventing
public harm that public law traditionally was considered "supe
[*303] rior" to private law. n224 Public law was inherently a
"subordinating" and "regulatory" law n225 in that it
"subordinated individual to public interests" as it regulated to
prevent public harm. n226 In fact, "public law" and "regulatory
law" are often used as synonyms in economic and commercial contexts. n227
Although private law also has a regulatory aspect to the extent that it seeks
to help order and define relations between individuals, public law regulates
the relations between individuals and society, even when operating indirectly
by regulating relations between individuals. n228
This subordinating aspect of public law also made most public laws
mandatory, and "it is the essence of mandatory rules that they defeat [any
contrary] agreement of the parties." n229 Mandatory rules are "rules
of law of a country which cannot be derogated from by contract." n230 A
mandatory law "applies irrespective of or despite the proper law of a
contract," whether determined by a contractual choice of law clause or the
conflicts rules that apply in the absence of a contractual designation. n231 In
that sense, mandatory laws are largely equivalent to laws within that prong of
the public law taboo forbidding the displacement of forum public law. In fact,
the definitions of mandatory law and public law often [*304] seem
to merge. Mandatory law, like public law, is said to be "designed to
protect the public interest ... or the ... weaker against a stronger
party." n232 Thus, "antitrust law is regulatory law [and] ... is
necessarily mandatory." n233
In contrast, nonmandatory law, like private law, "[exists]
mainly to provide private parties with a solution to their disputes in case
they have not done so themselves." n234 Nonmandatory law operates only to
the extent the parties to a transaction do not contractually elect different
applicable law or otherwise make their own governing contractual provisions.
n235 In other words, nonmandatory laws serve essentially in a default capacity,
and govern only in the event that, and only to the extent that, the parties
choose not to govern themselves otherwise.
If, in fact, all public laws were mandatory and all private laws
were nonmandatory, as their traditional definitions imply, this difference
alone probably would be sufficiently discernible to ensure the continuing
usefulness of the public law/private law distinction as the means by which the
public law taboo is enforced. Unfortunately, however, just as public law
sometimes addresses private interests and private law public interests, private
law can be mandatory too. n236 The host of potentially invalidating mandatory
contract rules - e.g., prohibitions of covenants not to compete, usury
restrictions, competency and capacity rules, statutes of frauds - illustrates
this fact.
There is, however, one significant, and perhaps saving difference
(at least in terms of enforcing the public law taboo) between mandatory public
laws and mandatory private laws: Although both are enforced irrespective of
contrary private party agreements in purely domestic transactions, that remains
true only of mandatory public laws in international transactions. In
international transactions, mandatory private laws traditionally are eligible
for choice of law analysis, including possible displacement by a contractual
election or conflicts analysis designating the law of another nation as
applicable. n237 This difference presumably re [*305] flects the
different levels of public interest reflected in private and public law: Even
if private law is mandatory in a domestic context, the public interest in the
enforcement of private law in an international transaction is not sufficient to
insist on application of the law without regard for the expectations of the
parties, the impact on cross-border commerce, and the comparative interests of
other states. n238 Thus, even though both public and private laws can be
mandatory, only mandatory public laws traditionally are mandatory in a
conflicts sense such that they cannot be displaced, if otherwise applicable, by
contractual election or choice of law analysis.
B. Toward a Workable Public Law/Private Law Distinction
These traditional definitions suggest essentially three categories
of law for purposes of applying the public law taboo: (1) mandatory public law,
to which the taboo applies and which, consequently, is ineligible for
contractual election and choice of law analysis, (2) nonmandatory public law,
to which the taboo may or may not apply depending on the reasons for the law's
failure to qualify as mandatory, and (3) private law, whether mandatory or not,
to which the taboo does not apply and which, consequently, is eligible for
possible displacement in international transactions by contractual election or
choice of law analysis. I believe that these categories can be reasonably and
reliably distinguished by courts and lawyers according to the two dimensions
suggested by the "mandatory public law" nomenclature and the
traditional definitions of private law and public law: a private/public
dimension and a mandatory/nonmandatory dimension.
The private/public dimension attempts to measure those aspects of
the traditional private law/public law distinction that focus on private
relationships versus public relationships, private interests versus public
interests, and private harms versus public harms. Essentially, the
private/public dimension is a measurement of the externalities likely to result
either from noncompliance with or repeal of the law or provision of law in
question. n239 Because common sense and economic analysis [*306] have
revealed that laws typically affect public and private relationships, serve
public along with private interests, and attempt to prevent public as well as
private harms, their private/public dimension necessarily falls along somewhat
of a continuum. Consequently, the outcome of the classification is a question
of predominance.
To illustrate with a few rather obvious examples, n240 most would
agree that noncompliance with or repeal of the contract rules of the Uniform
Commercial Code ("UCC") n241 ordinarily would produce fewer
externalities than would noncompliance with or repeal of the Sherman Act n242
or the Securities Acts, n243 and therefore that the UCC should be classified as
a private law, while the Sherman and Securities Acts should be classified as
public laws. Private relationships, interests, and harms are the predominant
concern of the UCC; public relationships, interests, and harms are the
predominant concerns of the Sherman and Securities Acts.
Similar respective classifications would result between the Jones
Act, n244 on the one hand, and the Federal Bills of Lading Act n245 and
Carriage of Goods by Sea Act ("COGSA"), n246 on the other. Although
all three Acts are federal statutes dealing, at least in part, with ocean-going
transport, and although all three statutes create causes of action in favor of
aggrieved private individuals, the Jones Act simply provides a mechanism for
certain seamen to assert private tort claims in federal court. n247 The Bills
of Lading Act and COGSA, in contrast, impose certain minimum duties on carriers
with respect to bills of lading, n248 and COGSA additionally imposes certain
minimum duties on carriers with respect to the seaworthiness of covered
vessels. n249 The repeal of all three Acts likely would reveal the Jones Act as
merely the statutory codification of a rule [*307] of private law,
but the Federal Bills of Lading and COGSA as laws intended primarily to serve
the public interest and prevent public harm.
Importantly, when assessing the degree of externalities likely to
result from noncompliance with or repeal of a particular law, the
private/public dimension focuses on the particular law at issue and not on the
particular transaction to which the law is applied. The dimension is intended
to categorize laws for purposes of the public law taboo, not transactions. In
any given case, noncompliance with a particular rule of contract law or
standard of reasonable care could have externalities comparatively greater than
those likely to result from any given violation of the Sherman Act or
Securities Acts. But the purpose of the measure is not to rank the severity of
actual public harm in any given case; instead, it is to help identify laws or
provisions of law whose public purpose is significant enough that they should
not be subject to displacement by private contractual election or judicial
comparative interest balancing. n250
A law's classification as public law, however, is alone not enough
for application of the public law taboo; the law also must be assessed
according to the mandatory/nonmandatory dimension. This dimension reflects the
"regulatory" aspect of the traditional public law definition - i.e.,
the fact that public law is a "subordinating law," subordinating
individual discretion and private law while regulating for the public good. One
measure of the mandatory/nonmandatory dimension, consequently, is the extent to
which the law or provision of law in question restricts individual discretion
and "regulates" private conduct. A second measure, also essential, is
that the law or provision of law not be prospectively waivable.
One would expect these two measures of the mandatory/nonmandatory
dimension to coincide. If a law restricts the exercise of private discretion in
a way intended to serve the public interest, the ability of persons protected
by the restriction to waive its protection prospectively obviously could defeat
the purpose of the restriction. It would not make much sense for the Sherman
Act, for example, to forbid agreements in restraint of trade without also
effectively forbidding agreements prospectively waiving that protection. Thus,
the protections afforded by the Sherman Act are not generally regarded as
prospectively waivable. n251 The Securities Acts and their explicit antiwaiver
provi [*308] sions n252 reflect a similar coincidence of regulated
discretion and the nonwaivability of intended protections (at least until the
wrongly decided Lloyd's cases altered that proposition n253), and the same
coincidence occurs in the Federal Bills of Lading Act and COGSA. n254 Indeed, a
presumption would seem appropriate that a public regulatory law is not
prospectively waivable without some affirmative indication of waivability
explicit in the law.
But the coincidence of restricted discretion and nonwaivable
protections need not always occur in public laws. When they do not, it is
appropriate that the law or provision of law not qualify for automatic
application of the public law taboo. For example, if the protection of a public
law may be prospectively waived by an individual for whom the protection is
intended, it would make little sense to apply the public law taboo to forbid
the contractual election by that individual of different applicable law if the
election meets whatever requirements the displaced law imposes on a prospective
waiver. If the same protected individual has not made a contrary contractual
election, however, it may make perfect sense to apply the taboo to forbid a
choice of law analysis that might displace the particular public law; the
ability to waive prospectively might be so integral to the particular law's
regulatory scheme (e.g., ensuring adequate compensation in exchange for the
waiver) that the law essentially is indistinguishable from a mandatory public
law. Of course, a public law might provide for a prospective waiver that is so
easily obtainable that the law should be regarded as potentially displaceable
by ordinary conflicts principles. n255
It is important to distinguish in this regard between the
prospective waivability of the protections of a public law, which renders the
law effectively nonmandatory, and the discretion individuals typically enjoy to
compromise or settle claims privately arising under mandatory public law. Why,
some might ask, should the public law taboo automatically prevent the
contractual or choice of law displacement of mandatory public law if claims
arising under such laws may be privately compromised in the complete discretion
of the claimant? How is the exercise of discretion in compromising a claim
different from the discretion exercised in a prospective waiver, which in some
circumstances may render the public law subject to possible displacement? The
answer, I believe, is simple: [*309] There is no reason to expect
the released party in the case of a pre-claim prospective waiver to conform to
the waived requirements of the public law at issue, but there is every reason
to expect a post-claim compromise to require substantial compliance with the
requirements of the law, insofar as the claim otherwise would be enforceable in
court. Thus, public law loses its mandatory character in the event of a
prospective waiver, but essentially retains it in the event of a post-claim
compromise.
A slightly different question also might arise: If nonmandatory
public law can be treated like private law for conflicts purposes, why not
treat mandatory private law like mandatory public law for purposes of the
public law taboo? The short answer resides in the public/private distinction:
the fact that a law is a public law rather than private law potentially
elevates its relative importance sufficiently so as automatically to outweigh
the expectations of private parties and regulatory interests of other nations
that typically are weighed in a conflicts analysis. Thus arises the
"public law taboo." But this is not to say that the relative
importance of mandatory private law in comparison to nonmandatory law is
nowhere expressed in conflicts analysis; to the contrary, it is fully reflected
in the "public policy exception" to conflicts analysis. When properly
applied, this much-maligned principle n256 holds that, when a contractual
election or the forum's conflicts rules point to foreign law as applicable law,
the forum's public policy still may override that designation in favor of forum
law - most typically, the forum's mandatory private law. n257 The forum's
mandatory private laws are simply eligible for conflicts analysis; they are not
necessarily displaced by it. n258
The analytical task of categorizing laws or provisions of law as
"public" or "private" and "mandatory" or
"nonmandatory" is far more appropriate for and typical of judicial
decisionmaking in a regulatory context than the task of identifying and
weighing the relative interests of all na [*310] tions in an
international transaction in order to determine the single nation to which
regulatory responsibility will be assigned. The categorization assessment does
not turn on the existence or degree of conflict among laws, the significance or
insignificance of different states' interests in the transaction, or what the
parties may or may not have expected; it instead focuses on the internal
characteristics of the law and reaches a conclusion either that the law,
because of its public classification, applies of its own force independent of
extraneous factors, or that the law, because of its private classification, is
eligible for displacement by possibly greater interests. n259 Significantly,
though, the fact that a law is within the public law taboo does not mean that
its extraterritorial scope is unlimited. The taboo means only that the law's
jurisdictional reach is not limited by contractual choice of law or conflicts
principles. Congress may constrain the jurisdictional reach of public laws in
whatever way it deems appropriate. n260
VII. Conclusion
The displacement of applicable law in international transactions
as a result of private contractual election or judicial conflicts analysis is
an extraordinary event, sometimes helpful to the advancement of private
commercial interests, but potentially injurious to the public good if not
appropriately constrained. The "public law taboo" traditionally
provided an appropriate constraint, safeguarding from possible displacement
"public laws" whose purposes were to advance public interests and
prevent public harms, and whose applicability more appropriately turned
exclusively on legislative intent. Although the eventual erosion of that
constraint was well meaning - intended, as it was, to reduce conflict among laws
and increase predictability for international commerce by identifying a single,
"most appropriate" regulatory jurisdiction for every international
issue or transaction - its actual effect on international commerce has been
deleterious.
The erosion of public law constraints on contractual choice of law
and conflicts principles, for example, has created a serious risk of
underregulation of international commerce. Parties to international transac
[*311] tions do not contractually opt out of a given national
regulatory scheme or litigate its inapplicability because of a desire for more
stringent or burdensome regulation elsewhere. Whenever applicable public law is
displaced, the likelihood is that it will be replaced by lesser regulation or a
regulatory void, with a possible consequence being the occurrence of precisely
the harm that the displaced public law was intended to prevent.
Moreover, the application to public law of the comparative
interest balancing principles of conflict of laws has significantly reduced,
rather than increased, predictability for international transactions. Interest
balancing is inherently backward looking; it is invoked only as a defense in
litigation to the application of a particular public law, and its only
predictable consequence for international commerce is a significant escalation
of litigation risks and costs. The ex ante certainty that the public law of
even multiple jurisdictions will apply to an international transaction if the
transaction exceeds some threshold of contacts within each jurisdiction (either
by virtue of conduct or effects) is far more predictable and beneficial for
international commerce than any ex post interest balancing determination of a
single applicable law. Only the former situation permits participants in
international transactions to account for (or avoid) the cost of compliance in
initially structuring their transactions, and only the former situation permits
regulating nations to weigh knowingly the benefits and costs of their
regulations.
For these reasons, courts should renew their efforts, as the
Supreme Court did in Hartford Fire, to differentiate between laws whose public
importance is significant enough to warrant disallowing displacement by
contractual election or conflicts analysis, and laws that appropriately should
remain eligible for displacement in international transactions. The traditional
public law/private law dichotomy facilitates this differentiation.
Specifically, the traditional public law/private law dichotomy
expresses two dimensions of a law's character that are susceptible to judicial
identification and measurement and enable a law's classification for purposes
of applying the public law taboo: a public/private dimension and a
mandatory/nonmandatory dimension. The former effectively measures the
externalities likely to result from noncompliance with or repeal of a law. The
latter assesses whether a law regulates private discretion and is not
prospectively waivable. The public/private dimension necessarily is a
continuum, and the classification outcome a question of predominance: the
greater the externalities, the more likely a law should be classified as
"public"; the fewer the externalities, the more appropriate a
classification as "private." The mandatory/nonmandatory dimension is
more binary in nature: A law that restricts private discretion and that is not
prospectively waivable is mandatory, while a law that does not restrict private
discretion or is prospectively waivable is nonmandatory.
Mandatory public laws automatically should fall within the public
law taboo. Nonmandatory public laws should fall within or outside of the taboo
depending on the reason for their failure to qualify as mandatory.
[*312] All private law, whether mandatory or not, should fall outside
the taboo and remain eligible for possible displacement by contractual election
or conflicts analysis. This system of classification will be meaningful and
manageable for courts and for participants in international transactions. It
will safeguard from possible displacement those laws whose public importance is
significant enough that they should apply irrespective of private interests or
the interests of other nations, and it will reserve for the political arena,
instead of an ill-equipped judiciary, any accommodation of public laws that is
necessary because of overlapping regulatory interests of several nations.
FOOTNOTES:
n1. This Article, throughout its entirety, will use the phrases
"conflicts rules," "conflict of laws principles,"
"conflicts," "conflicts principles," and "choice of
law principles" to refer generally to the comparative interest balancing
of various nations' relationships to any given international transaction. This
is characteristic of most approaches to contract conflict of laws. See text
accompanying note 40 and the last sentence of note 50, infra, for further
explanation of this usage. I will be explicit whenever I use any of these
phrases in a more refined way. In this Article, the phrases "conflicts
principles" and "choice of law principles" include contractual
autonomy to select applicable law (often referred to in the literature as
"party autonomy") unless otherwise specified. This usage is
consistent with the convention in traditional conflicts scholarship of including
contractual autonomy to select applicable law as an aspect of conflict of laws.
n2. The phrase "public law taboo" seems to have
originated with Professor Lowenfeld. See Andreas F. Lowenfeld, Public Law in
the International Arena: Conflict of Laws, International Law and Some
Suggestions for Their Interaction, 163 Recueil Des Cours 311, 322 (1979)
[hereinafter Lowenfeld, Public Law]. It may have been just as accurate to
declare a "conflicts taboo" in the realm of public law, but this
Article will continue to use Professor Lowenfeld's apt convention.
n3. Carol Harlow, "Public" and "Private" Law:
Definition Without Distinction, 43 Mod. L. Rev. 241, 256 (1980).
n4. See Harold G. Maier, Extraterritorial Jurisdiction at a
Crossroads: An Intersection Between Public and Private International Law, 76
Am. J. Int'l L. 280, 299 (1982) [hereinafter Maier, Extraterritorial
Jurisdiction]; see also Donald T. Trautman, The Role of Conflicts Thinking in
Defining the International Reach of American Regulatory Legislation, 22 Ohio
St. L.J. 586, 590-91 (1961).
n5. See, e.g., Mannington Mills, Inc. v. Congoleum Corp., 595 F.2d
1287 (3d Cir. 1979); Timberlane Lumber Co. v. Bank of Am., 549 F.2d 597 (9th
Cir. 1976).
n6. Restatement (Third) of Foreign Relations Law 401-03 (1987).
n7. See Richards v. Lloyd's of London, 135 F.3d 1289 (9th Cir.
1998); Lipcon v. Underwriters at Lloyd's, London, 148 F.3d 1285 (11th Cir.
1998); Haynsworth v. The Corporation, 121 F.3d 956 (5th Cir. 1997); Allen v.
Lloyd's of London, 94 F.3d 923 (4th Cir. 1996); Roby v. Corporation of Lloyd's,
996 F.2d 1353 (2d Cir. 1993); Bonny v. Society of Lloyd's, 3 F.3d 156 (7th Cir. 1993); Riley v.
Kingsley Underwriting Agencies, Ltd., 969 F.2d 953 (10th Cir. 1992). The Sixth
Circuit relied on identical reasoning to displace state securities law claims
in Shell v. R.W. Sturge, Ltd., 55 F.3d 1227 (6th Cir. 1995).
n8. In this respect, it is important to distinguish between the
displacement of forum public law and the recognition and enforcement of foreign
public law, both of which are aspects of the traditional public law taboo.
Whereas the former presents risks of significant underregulation of
international commerce, the latter may have pro-regulatory effects. See infra
text accompanying notes 151-153.
n9. 509 U.S. 764 (1993).
n10. The Supreme Court's international arbitration cases, of
course, do extend principles of contractual autonomy to the arbitration of
public law claims. See Vimar Seguros Y Reaseguros, S.A. v. M/V Sky Reefer, 515
U.S. 528 (1995) (regarding the Carriage of Goods by Sea Act); Mitsubishi Motors
Corp. v. Soler Chrysler-Plymouth, Inc., 473 U.S. 614 (1985) (regarding the
Sherman Act); Scherk v. Alberto-Culver Co., 417 U.S. 506 (1974) (regarding the
Securities Exchange Act of 1934). Yet, none of these cases suggests that
applicable U.S. public law may be displaced by contractual election. Because
these cases clearly suggest that forum differences often will be accommodated
with respect to public law issues, they imply that the Supreme Court might be
willing to abandon the public law/private law distinction in the context of
permitting U.S. courts to recognize and apply foreign public law even though
the Court is not willing to abandon that distinction with respect to the
displacement of forum public law. See infra text accompanying notes 130-132 and
accompanying text.
n11. 345 U.S. 571 (1953).
n12. 46 U.S.C. app. 688 (1994). The Jones Act provides that
qualified injured seamen may bring personal injury suits (essentially common
law tort claims) in federal court.
n13. 46 U.S.C. app. 1300-15 (1994).
n14. 17 U.S.C. 1101 (1994).
n15. See Hans W. Baade, The Operation of Foreign Public Law, 30
Tex. Int'l L.J. 429, 447, 478 (1995); Andreas F. Lowenfeld, International
Litigation and Arbitration 1 (1993) [hereinafter Lowenfeld, International
Litigation] ("Traditionally, in all countries, conflict of laws has been
confined to controversies under private law."). This principle is also
reflected in the organization of private law by category in most leading conflicts
of laws treatises' tables of contents. See Eugene F. Scoles & Peter Hay,
Conflict of Laws (2d ed. 1992); Russell J. Weintraub, Commentary on the
Conflict of Laws (3d ed. 1986) [hereinafter Weintraub, Commentary].
n16. Restatement (Second) of Conflicts of Law 188 (1971).
n17. Convention on the Law Applicable to Contractual Obligations,
opened for signature June 19, 1980, art. 4 O.J. (L 266) 1 (EEC) [hereinafter
CLACO].
n18. See Restatement (First) of Conflicts of Law 332 (1934).
n19. See Weintraub, Commentary, supra note 15, at 397-98; Larry
Kramer, Rethinking Choice of Law, 90 Colum. L. Rev. 277, 329-34 (1990).
n20. The term "party autonomy," as used to indicate the
parties' ability to designate the law that will apply to an international
transaction, is something of a "stepchild" in conflicts theory
insofar as none of the dominant approaches to contractual choice of law even
considers party preference as to governing law. Patrick J. Borchers, The
Internationalization of Contractual Conflicts Law, 28 Vand. J. Transnat'l L.
421, 436 (1995); Edith Friedler, Party Autonomy Revisited: A Statutory Solution
to a Choice-of-Law Problem, 37 U. Kan. L. Rev. 471, 472-84 (1989); see also
supra notes 15-18 and accompanying text. Nonetheless, party autonomy has been
called "perhaps the most widely accepted private international law rule of
our time." Russell J. Weintraub, Functional Developments in Choice of Law
for Contracts, 187 Recueil des Cours 239, 271 (1984) [hereinafter Weintraub,
Functional Developments]. It has been recognized as a doctrine of conflict of
laws since the nineteenth century in the United States, the eighteenth century
in England, and even centuries earlier on the European Continent. See Ian F. G.
Baxter, International Business and Choice of Law, 36 Int'l & Comp. L.Q. 92,
95 (1987); Borchers, supra, at 432; Friedler, supra, at 471; Hessel E. Yntema,
"Autonomy" in Choice of Law, 1 Am. J. Comp. L. 341, 348-51 (1952)
[hereinafter Yntema, "Autonomy"]. The states or nations whose laws
parties may contractually designate as governing sometimes are limited to those
with a "reasonable relation" to the parties or their transaction.
U.C.C. 1-105(1) (1997), 1 U.L.A. 29 (1989). More often, however, party choice
is unrestricted in this regard. See, e.g., Borchers, supra, at 433.
n21. See Scoles & Hay, supra note 15, at 658-734 (summarizing
approaches to contracts choice of law); Weintraub, Commentary, supra note 15,
at 362-411 (summarizing approaches to contracts choice of law).
n22. See, e.g., U.C.C. 1-105(1) (1997), 1 U.L.A. 29 (1989)
("Except as provided hereafter in this section, when a transaction bears a
reasonable relation to this state and also to another state or nation the
parties may agree that the law either of this state or of such other state or
nation shall govern their rights and duties."); U.N. Conference on
Contracts for the International Sale of Goods art. 6, U.N. Doc. A/Conf. 97/18
(1980), 52 Fed. Reg. 6264 (1987), 19 I.L.M. 668 (1980) [hereinafter CISG]
("The parties may exclude the application of this Convention or, subject
to [the article concerning a writing], derogate from or vary the effect of any
of its provisions."). Section 187 of the Restatement (Second) of Conflict
of Laws, concerning the "Law of the State Chosen by the Parties," is
also silent about the public law boundaries that traditionally have confined
its provisions. It does, however, suggest that a "fundamental policy"
of a state with a "materially greater interest" in the particular
issue than the chosen state might negate the parties' choice. See Restatement
(Second) of Conflict of Laws 187(2)(b) (1971). See also infra note 32 and
accompanying text.
n23. See Holman v. Johnson, 1 Cowp. 341, 343 (1775) (Mansfield,
J.) ("No country ever takes notice of the revenue laws of another.");
Restatement (First) of Conflict of Laws 610 (1934) ("No action can be
maintained on a right created by the law of a foreign state as a method of
furthering its own governmental interests."); A.V. Dicey & J.H.C.
Morris, The Conflict of Laws 75 (J.H.C. Morris ed., 9th ed. 1973) (noting that
courts "have no jurisdiction to entertain an action ... for the
enforcement ... of a penal, revenue, or other public law of a foreign
State"); Lowenfeld, International Litigation, supra note 15, at 1
("If...a controversy before the court concerns a ... public law, the
thought that State A might apply the law of State B seems to be out of the
question. In such cases, the forum either applies its own law, or if there is
no basis for doing that, dismisses the action."); see also, e.g., Roby v.
Corp. of Lloyd's, 996 F.2d 1353, 1362 (2d Cir. 1993)("Neither an English
court nor an English arbitrator would apply the United States securities laws,
because English conflict of law rules do not permit recognition of foreign tort
or statutory law.").
n24. Judge Learned Hand once hypothesized that the rationale for
this aspect of the public law taboo was a dual concern about the impropriety of
scrutinizing another sovereign's law and the impropriety of a court enforcing a
law it hasn't scrutinized. See Moore v. Mitchell, 30 F.2d 600, 604 (2d Cir.
1929); see also Maier, Extraterritorial Jurisdiction, supra note 4, at 290.
n25. See Lowenfeld, International Litigation, supra note 15, at 1;
William S. Dodge, Extraterritoriality and Conflict-of-Laws Theory: An Argument
for Judicial Unilateralism, 39 Harv. Int'l L. J. 101, 109 (1998) (noting that,
"A U.S. court will apply foreign tort or contract law to decide a case
before it, but it will not apply foreign regulatory law like antitrust law. If
foreign law is deemed to govern in an antitrust case, the court will simply
dismiss..."). Recently, however, that aspect of the public law taboo
concerning the enforcement of foreign public law has begun to erode. See infra
Part III.D; see also supra note 10 and accompanying text.
n26. Henri Batiffol, Public Policy and the Autonomy of the
Parties: Interrelations between Imperative Legislation and the Doctrine of
Party Autonomy, in Lectures on the Conflicts of Law and International Contracts
68, 79 (Hessel E. Yntema reprint ed., 1982) (quoting Ernst Rabel, 2 The
Conflict of Laws: A Comparative Study (1947)). See also Compania de Inversiones
Internationales v. Industrial Mortgage Bank of Finland, 198 N.E. 617, 621
(1935), cert. denied, 297 U.S. 705 (1936) ("The joint resolution [of
Congress] has thus revealed clearly the intention of the Congress to regulate
the kind and amount of the currency wherewith the obligation may be
discharged....The parties to a contract may not by their intention, however
expressed, override the [public] laws of the country in which suit is
brought....").
n27. Yntema, "Autonomy," supra note 20, at 343. See
also, e.g., Knott v. Botany Mills, 179 U.S. 69, 71 (1900) (nullifying a
contractual choice of law clause that, if given effect, would have displaced
mandatory provisions of the U.S. Harter Act of 1893 (codified as amended at 46
U.S.C. 190-96 (1994))). This same rule should apply as well to forum selection
and arbitration clauses: a nonselected forum should not dismiss an action subject
to such a clause if to do so would result in the displacement of mandatory
forum public law. See, e.g., Mitsubishi Motors Corp. v. Soler Chrysler-Plymouth
Inc., 473 U.S. 614, 637 n.19 (1985) (noting that the Court "would have
little hesitation in condemning" a contract in which "the
choice-of-forum and choice-of-law clauses operated in tandem as a prospective
waiver of a party's right to pursue statutory remedies"); Akai Party Ltd.
v. The People's Ins. Co. Ltd., (1996) 71 A.L.R. 156 (Austl.) (refusing to
enforce choice-of-forum and choice-of-law clauses in an insurance contract
designating an English forum and English law when enforcement of choice clauses
would displace the Australian Insurance Contracts Act of 1984); The Hollandia,
[1983] App. Cas. 565, 574-75 (H.L. 1982) (appeal taken from Eng.) (refusing
enforcement of a choice-of-forum clause that would have displaced the
applicable English Carriage of Goods by Sea Act (1971)); Weintraub, Functional
Development, supra note 20, at 296 ("If a forum's mandatory rule ... would
not yield to a clause choosing the law of another country, then it is
inconsistent to permit forum law to be evaded by a clause requiring litigation
in a court that would not apply the forum's mandatory rule.").
n28. See, e.g., Batiffol, supra note 26, at 79; Bernardo M.
Cremades & Steven L. Plehn, The New Lex Mercatoria and the Harmonization of
the Laws of International Commercial Transactions, 2 B.U. Int'l L.J. 317, 325
n.37 (1984) ("Contractual freedom and ... mandatory national laws are
different sides of the same coin; one begins where the other one ends.");
Joel R. Paul, Comity in International Law, 32 Harv. Int'l L.J. 1, 28 (1991)
(noting that European courts use "the principles of loi de police or ordre
public to supersede other conflict-of-laws rules and impose domestic law
without regard for the public policy of the foreign sovereign"); Hans
Smit, The Future of International Commercial Arbitration: A Single
Transnational Institution?, 25 Colum. J. Transnat'l L. 9, 23 (1986) ("The
autonomy of parties in choosing the applicable law is not absolute; for
example, the parties may not ... evade mandatory rules of law that would
otherwise be applicable."); Michael Whincop & Mary Keyes, Putting the
"Private' Back Into Private International Law: Default Rules and the
Proper Law of the Contract, 21 Melb. U. L. Rev. 515, 521 (1997) (noting that,
"subject to normal questions of statutory interpretation ... courts will
apply mandatory legislative provisions of the forum notwithstanding the choice
of another legal system as the proper law of the contract"); Yntema,
"Autonomy," supra note 20, at 343.
n29. Article 7(2) of the Convention, which limits both party
autonomy to choose applicable law as stipulated in article 3(1) and the choice
of law rules that apply in the absence of party choice as promulgated in
article 4, provides that, "nothing in this Convention shall restrict the
application of the rules of law of the forum in a situation where they are
mandatory irrespective of the law otherwise applicable to the contract."
CLACO, supra note 17, arts. 3(1), 4, 7(2). The official report on the
Convention notes that, "The origin of [article 7(2)] is found in the
concern of certain delegations to safeguard the rules of the law of the forum
(notably rules on cartels, competition and restrictive practices, consumer
protection and certain rules concerning carriage) which are mandatory in the
situation whatever the law applicable to the contract may be." See Mario
Giuliano & Paul Lagarde, Report on the Convention on the Law Applicable to
Contractual Obligations, 1980 O.J. (c 282) 1, 28.
n30. Loucks v. Standard Oil Co., 224 N.Y. 99, 111 (1918)
(concerning a conflict between the New York and Massachusetts approaches to the
doctrine of respondeat superior).
n31. CLACO, supra note 17, art. 16.
n32. See Restatement (Second) of Conflict of Laws 187(2)(b)
(1971)(noting that party designated law need not be applied if "contrary
to a fundamental policy of a state which has a materially greater interest ...
and which, under the rule of 188, would be the state of the applicable law in
the absence of an effective choice of law by the parties"). Unlike the
traditional "public policy" exception, section 187 of the Second
Restatement obviously contemplates that the public policy of the state whose
law would have applied in the absence of the party designation also may limit
the application of party designated law, regardless of the forum state. Also,
unlike the traditional formulation, this section of the Restatement speaks of a
"fundamental policy" exception rather than a "public
policy" exception. There has been some scholarly discussion about whether
or not those two concepts are identical in practice. See, e.g., Friedler, supra
note 20, at 491-92, 512-13; Richard J. Bauerfield, Note, Effectiveness of
Choice-of-Law Clauses in Contract Conflicts of Law: Party Autonomy or Objective
Determination?, 82 Colum. L. Rev. 1659, 1675 n.106 (1982) [hereinafter
Bauerfield, Note, Effectiveness of Choice-of-Law Clauses]. The public policy
exception is not explicit in section 188 of the Second Restatement, which
establishes a "most significant relationship" standard for
determining the law applicable to a transaction in the absence of an effective
choice by the parties. The traditional universality of the public policy
exception implicitly would seem to modify section 188, however, at least when
the law having the "most significant relationship to the transaction and
the parties" is not also the law of the forum. Restatement (Second) of
Conflict of Laws 188 (1971). Section 6 of the Second Restatement arguably
imposes the exception explicitly by requiring the forum court to "follow a
statutory directive of its own state on choice of law," or to consider
"the relevant policies of the forum" if there is none. Id. 6.
n33. See Monrad G. Paulsen & Michael I. Sovern, "Public
Policy" in the Conflict of Laws, 56 Colum. L. Rev. 969, 987 (1956) (noting
that public policy easily can "serve as a substitute for thinking");
Borchers, supra note 20, app. B at 462 (attaching a letter from Professor Larry
Kramer asserting that "judges frequently and easily use [the Second
Restatement's fundamental policy exception] to avoid the parties'
choice"); David Clifford Burger, Note, Transnational Public Policy as a
Factor in Choice of Law Analysis, 5 N.Y.L. Sch. J. Int'l & Comp. L. 367,
369 (1984) [hereinafter Burger, Transnational Public Policy] (noting "the
failure of the current conception of public policy to provide a structured,
analytical framework for choice of law purposes"); Bauerfield, Note,
Effectiveness of Choice-of-Law Clauses, supra note 32, at 1675 (noting that a
review of the case law had revealed that "courts too readily invoke the
[public policy] exception in lieu of careful analysis").
n34. One commenator has noted:
Employing [the principle of public policy], a court would first be
directed to apply foreign law under ordinary choice of law analysis. After an
examination of the foreign law, however, the court [might] find the foreign law
or its effect at odds with fundamental principles of the forum, and thus reject
application of the offensive foreign law.".
Burger, Transnational Public Policy, supra note 33, at 377.
n35. The outcomes of these and similar issues vary. See, e.g., Woods-Tucker
Leasing Corp. v. Hutcheson-Ingram Dev. Co., 642 F.2d 744, 750-51 (5th Cir.
1981) (regarding usury issues and conflicts analysis); Restatement (Second)
Conflict of Laws 203 (1971) (suggesting a rule of validation for usury issues
if "not greatly in excess" of the rate permitted by the "state
of the otherwise applicable law"); Bauerfield, Note, Effectiveness of
Choice-of-Law Clauses, supra note 32, at 1672-73. Questions of public policy
most often arise when the issue of applicable law affects contract validity as
opposed to simply its construction or interpretation. See, e.g., Weintraub,
Commentary, supra note 15, at 362-63; Weintraub, Functional Developments, supra
note 20, at 252-54, 272. See also infra Part VI.B, with emphasis on text
accompanying notes 236-238 (discussing why the typically mandatory private laws
mentioned in the above text remain within the scope of conflicts analysis,
while mandatory public laws such as antitrust and securities fall outside its
scope).
n36. This proposition is illustrated by the fact that the European
Community's Convention on the Law Applicable to Contractual Obligations deals
with the public law taboo and the public policy exception in separate articles.
See CLACO, supra note 17, arts. 7, 16.
n37. See Richards v. Lloyd's of London, 135 F.3d 1289 (9th Cir.
1998); Lipcon v. Underwriters at Lloyd's, London, 148 F.3d 1285 (11th Cir.
1998); Haynsworth v. The Corporation, 121 F.3d 956 (5th Cir. 1997); Allen v.
Lloyd's of London, 94 F.3d 923 (4th Cir. 1996); Roby v. Corp. of Lloyd's, 996
F.2d 1353 (2d Cir. 1993); Bonny v. Society of Lloyd's, 3 F.3d 156 (7th Cir. 1993); Riley v.
Kingsley Underwriting Agencies, Ltd., 969 F.2d 953 (10th Cir. 1992).
n38. See O. Kahn-Freund, General Problems of Private International
Law 149 (1976) ("We know that no country applies a foreign rule if the
result of doing so would be at variance with its fundamental principles and
policies."); Paul, supra note 28, at 34-35 ("Civil-law courts have
liberally applied public policy exceptions ... to block the operation of
offending foreign laws.").
n39. Baade, supra note 15, at 453 (emphasis added). As Professor
Baade's reference to "ordre public international" suggests, nations
often distinguish between international public policy and domestic public
policy, with the scope of the former being much narrower than the scope of the
latter. Only the former, moreover, applies in an international conflict of laws
setting, thereby permitting the domestic application of a foreign law that is
different from forum law, but not so different that its application offends the
forum's notions of international public policy. International public policy
still only applies in a private law context, however, and thus does not operate
to permit the displacement of forum public law.
n40. See supra Part II.A, particularly text accompanying notes
16-19; Albert A. Ehrenzweig, A Counter-Revolution in Conflicts Law? From Beale
to Cavers, 80 Harv. L. Rev. 377 (1966); Burger, Transnational Public Policy,
supra note 33, at 368 n.8.
n41. See Laker Airways Ltd. v. Sabena, Belgian World Airways, 731
F.2d 909, 922 (1984) ("When the national of one state causes substantial
effects in another state, both states may potentially have jurisdiction to
prescribe governing law. Thus, under international law, territoriality and
nationality often give rise to concurrent jurisdiction."); Baade, supra
note 15, at 443 ("International law ... contemplates concurrent and
possibly conflicting penal jurisdiction and hence, conflicting regulatory rules
enforced by penalties."). Jurisdiction to prescribe concerns the authority
of a state to make its law applicable to persons or activities. See Restatement
(Third) of Foreign Relations Law 401(a) (1988); Restatement (Second) of Foreign
Relations Law 6, 17, 18 (1965). Whether or not an exercise of prescriptive
jurisdiction is effective can turn on a state's jurisdiction to adjudicate,
which concerns the authority of a state to subject persons or things to its
judicial process (e.g., in personam jurisdiction and subject matter
jurisdiction), and on a state's jurisdiction to enforce, which concerns the
authority of a state to compel compliance or punish noncompliance with its
laws. Restatement (Third) of Foreign Relations Law 401(b)-(c).
n42. Section 40 of the Restatement (Second) of Foreign Relations
Law urged states to consider moderating their enforcement of properly
prescribed law when the laws of two states "require inconsistent conduct
upon the part of a person" (emphasis added). In that narrow situation,
each forum state was urged to consider the relative interests of all regulating
states. Id. 40(a). As Professor Maier has noted, "the reasonableness
requirement in section 40 is not relevant to whether prescriptive ...
jurisdiction exists ab initio." Maier, Extraterritorial Jurisdiction,
supra note 4, at 294 n.67. Accommodating such compulsion to act inconsistently
with properly prescribed law is essentially a purpose of the foreign sovereign
compulsion and act of state doctrine defenses. See generally Lowenfeld,
International Litigation, supra note 15, chs. 8-9.
n43. See Louise Weinberg, Against Comity, 80 Geo. L.J. 53, 61
(1991) ("In international cases... when defendants argue against
application of an act of Congress, courts are likely simply to construe the act
to discover the extraterritorial intention of Congress. In such cases foreign
law rarely enters the discussion."); Maier, Extraterritorial Jurisdiction,
supra note 4, at 291 ("In the regulatory cases, the Restatement (Second)
of Conflicts and the Restatement (Second) of Foreign Relations Law combine with
statutory construction maxims to encourage an analytical approach that
discourages overt consideration of the effect of an assertion of jurisdiction
to prescribe or enforce in light of the needs of the transnational legal
system."); Diane P. Wood, Conflicts of Jurisdiction in Antitrust Law: A
Comment on Ordover and Atwood, 50 Law & Contemp. Probs. 179, 183 (1987)
("Once a particular country is satisfied that its own claim to jurisdiction
is validly based, both the desirability and the need to adopt any conflict
avoidance mechanism vanishes.").
n44. 148 F.2d 416 (2d Cir. 1945).
n45. The Second Circuit in Alcoa was sitting as a court of last
resort by virtue of an assignment from the Supreme Court, which had been unable
to muster a quorum of six unrecused Justices to hear the case. See id. at 421.
The Supreme Court noted subsequently that this circumstance "adds" to
"[Alcoa's] weight as a precedent." American Tobacco Co. v. United
States, 328 U.S. 781, 811 (1946).
n46. See Sherman Act, 15 U.S.C. 1.
n47. See United States v. Aluminum Co. of Am., 148 F.2d at 439-43.
n48. See id. at 443-45.
n49. Id. at 443 (emphasis added). See infra notes 191 and
accompanying text, for a discussion of why the Supreme Court's later decision
in Lauritzen v. Larsen, 345 U.S. 571 (1952), does not contradict this assertion
by the Alcoa Court. In Lauritzen, the Court explicitly assessed the regulatory
interests of other nations in determining the jurisdictional reach of the Jones
Act, 46 U.S.C. 688, which allows injured seamen to maintain personal injury
damages actions in U.S. courts.
n50. The limits on prescriptive jurisdiction customarily observed
by nations at the time of the Alcoa decision (and as Part IV demonstrates)
obviously did not include deferring the exercise of otherwise permissible
jurisdiction to the "superior" interest of another state. See supra
notes 40-43 and accompanying text. Thus, Judge Hand's reference to "the
limitations customarily observed by nations upon the exercise of their
powers" and his subsequent equation of those limitations with the
"limitations which generally correspond to those fixed by the
"Conflict of Laws,'" 148 F.2d at 443, clearly did not mean that Judge
Hand was suggesting or using in his analysis of the jurisdictional reach of
U.S. antitrust law a "comparative interest balancing" approach to
resolving conflicts typical of the private law arena. See supra note 40 and
accompanying text. Instead, he explained the "limitations" to which
he referred exclusively in terms of the sufficiency of the relationship between
the transaction or activities and the nation whose prescriptive jurisdiction is
at issue. See infra text accompanying notes 51-52; see also Restatement (First)
of Conflicts 65 cmt. a (1934) ("If consequences of an act done in one
state occur in another state, each state in which any event in the series of
act and consequences occurs may exercise legislative jurisdiction ....").
One author has suggested that "conflict of laws" includes
noncomparative, "unilateral" approaches to determining the
jurisdictional reach of public law, and therefore, that it is improper to
suggest that courts traditionally have not applied a "conflict of
laws" approach to public law. See Dodge, supra note 25, at 143-44. I tend
to view that suggestion as mistaken, or at best, as splitting hairs, but in all
events, I am using in this Article the conventional understanding of the
relationship between public law and conflicts law - namely, that public law
traditionally has been outside the scope of conflict of laws/private
international law and not simply within a unilateralist school of conflicts
analysis.
n51. United States v. Aluminum Co. of Am., 148 F.2d at 444.
n52. Id. at 443. Judge Hand's statement of this
"traditional" rule obviously overlooked Justice Holmes' statement in
American Banana Co. v. United Fruit Co., 213 U.S. 347, 356 (1909), that,
"the general and almost universal rule is that the character of an act as
unlawful must be determined wholly by the law of the country where the act was
done." The American Banana Court consequently refused application of the
Sherman Act to an alleged conspiracy in Costa Rica between United Fruit Company
(an American corporation) and the Government of Costa Rica to prevent American
Banana Company (also an American company) from growing bananas in Costa Rica
and shipping them to the United States for sale. Although never formally
overruled, it seems clear that American Banana did not survive Alcoa. See, e.g.,
Russell J. Weintraub, The Extraterritorial Application of Antitrust and
Securities Laws: An Inquiry into the Utility of a "Choice-of-Law"
Approach, 70 Tex. L. Rev. 1799, 1808 (1992) [hereinafter Weintraub,
Extraterritorial Application]; Note, Extraterritorial Application of United
States Laws: A Conflict of Laws Approach, 28 Stan. L. Rev. 1005, 1009 n.23
(1976). The American Banana strict territorial approach to prescriptive
jurisdiction likely would result in different outcomes in many international transactions
than the Alcoa "intended effects" test, as well as a far greater
accommodation of foreign regulatory interests. That is, the American Banana
test typically results in a single nation having regulatory authority; the
Alcoa test permits regulation by multiple nations. However, both tests are
noncomparative in application insofar as each focuses on the sufficiency of a
transaction's contacts with the candidate regulating nation rather than on how
those contacts compare or "balance" in relation to the transaction's
contacts with other nations.
n53. Issues concerning the reach or scope of a nation's
prescriptive jurisdiction arise most typically when there is some
"extraterritorial" aspect to the application of the prescribing
nation's law, as when the objects of the particular regulatory assertion are
foreign nationals or conduct occurring abroad - factors present in most
multinational transactions. The "intended effects" test does not
result in an "extraterritorial" assertion of jurisdiction in the sense
that nothing of regulatory significance occurs in the regulating nation -
effects do. See, e.g., Laker Airways Limited v. Sabena, Belgian World Airways,
731 F.2d 909, 923 (1984). This Article's consideration of the
"extraterritorial" reach of public law is essentially confined to the
question of whether the judicial determination of that issue has included or
should include "comparative interest balancing" typical of conflict
of laws, or whether instead the judicial determination of that issue should be
confined to the traditionally non-comparative inquiry into Congressional intent
(i.e., this Article considers only whether it makes sense to restore a
categorical exemption of "mandatory public laws" from judicially
applied contract choice of law principles). I will not otherwise address in any
detail the important question of what rules of construction or other standards
should govern the judicial inquiry into issues of public law
"extraterritoriality." The literature on that question is abundant
and voluminous. See, e.g., Margaret Sachs, The International Reach of Rule
10b-5: The Myth of Congressional Silence, 28 Colum. J. Transnt'l L. 677, 682-83
n.23 (1990); see generally Jonathan Turley, When in Rome: Multinational
Misconduct and the Presumption Against Extraterritoriality, 84 Nw. U. L. Rev.
598 (1990); Symposium, Extraterritoriality of Economic Legislation, 50 Law
& Contemp. Probs., No. 3 (1987).
n54. The traditional bases of prescriptive jurisdiction, in
addition to "intended effects" within the prescribing territory, are
conduct within the territory of the prescribing nation and regulation of the
activities of nationals of the prescribing nation wherever the activities
occur. See Restatement (Second) of Foreign Relations Law 17 (1965); see also Maier,
Extraterritorial Jurisdiction, supra note 4, at 293 n.63 (identifying
additional bases of prescriptive jurisdiction outside of a commercial context,
such as when dealing with international terrorism).
n55. See discussion infra Part III, Subparts III.A and III.B.
n56. United States v. Aluminum Co. of Am., 148 F.2d at 443.
n57. Restatement (Second) of Foreign Relations Law 17(a).
n58. Restatement (Second) of Foreign Relations Law 18(b).
n59. See Maier, Extraterritorial Jurisdiction, supra note 4, at 292-93.
See supra note 42 and accompanying text for an explanation of why section 40 of
the Second Restatement of Foreign Relations does not undercut my assertion
about the Second Restatement's essentially non-comparative approach to
prescriptive jurisdiction.
n60. Most of the case law and commentary concerns the
international reach of the antifraud provisions of the Securities Exchange Act,
specifically Section 10(b) and Rule 10b-5 (Securities Exchange Act of 1934
10(b), 15 U.S.C. 78j(b) (1996) and 17 C.F.R. 240.10b-5 (1996)), which generally
prohibit any person from using the means and instrumentalities of interstate
commerce to effect fraudulent securities transactions. See generally Sachs,
supra note 53, at 682 n.19, 682-83 n.23; Turley, supra note 53, at 614. Other
provisions of the Securities Acts, including their registration and filing
requirements, do not have equally extensive international application. Id. See
also Robert Hacker & Ronald Rotunda, The Extraterritorial Regulation of
Foreign Business Under the U.S. Securities Laws, 59 N.C.L. Rev. 643, 649;
Weintraub, Extraterritorial Application, supra note 52, at 1814; 17 C.F.R.
230.901-.904 (1991) (establishing Regulation S, which eliminates the
requirement of registration under the Securities Act of 1933, 15 U.S.C. 77e
(1988) for offers and sales of securities that occur outside the United
States).
n61. See Robinson v. TCI/US West Cable Communications Inc., 117
F.3d 900, 904-05 (5th Cir. 1997).
The Exchange Act does [not explicitly] address the circumstances
under which American courts have subject matter jurisdiction to hear suits
involving foreign transactions.... The courts... have created two basic
tests[:] ... the "conduct' test, which in essence asks whether the
[allegedly] fraudulent conduct ... occurred in the United States, and the
"effects' test, which asks whether conduct outside the United States has
had a substantial adverse effect on American investors or securities markets.
Id.; see also Turley, supra note 53, at 613; Hacker & Rotunda,
supra note 60, at 656-66.
n62. See, e.g., Robinson, 117 F.3d at 905-06, in which the Fifth
Circuit stated:
The circuits are divided as to precisely what sort of activities
are needed to satisfy the conduct test.... The more restrictive position - that
the domestic conduct must have been of "material importance' to or have
"directly caused' the fraud complained of - is followed in the Second and
District of Columbia Circuits [which we now adopt].
See also, e.g., Alfadda v. Fenn, 935 F.2d 475, 478 (2d Cir. 1991)
(applying antifraud provisions because the "defendant's conduct in the
United States was more than merely preparatory to the fraud, and ... directly
caused losses to foreign investors abroad"); Bersch v. Drexel Firestone,
Inc., 519 F.2d 974, 989 (2d Cir. 1975) (applying antifraud provisions
"only when [the foreign acts] result in injury to purchasers or sellers
... in whom the United States has an interest, not where acts simply have an
adverse affect [sic] on the American economy or American investors
generally"); Leasco Data Processing Equipment Corp. v. Maxwell, 468 F.2d
1326, 1337 (2d Cir. 1972) ("It tips the scales in favor of applicability
when substantial misrepresentations were made in the United States.").
n63. The lack of a transaction's connection with the United
States, of course, often inevitably reveals a stronger connection between the
transaction and some other potential prescribing jurisdiction. See, e.g.,
Zoelsch v. Arthur Andersen & Co., 824 F.2d 27, 34 (D.C. Cir. 1987) (noting
that the fraudulent "core" occurred in West Germany and any
misrepresentations in the United States were not "sufficiently in
connection with the purchase or sale of any security"); Mormels v.
Girofinance, S.A., 544 F. Supp. 815, 818 (S.D.N.Y. 1982) (noting that
defendants committed the "crucial acts" of fraud in Costa Rica; any
U.S. acts were of a "secondary nature"). The basis of decisions
refusing to apply U.S. securities law still is the insufficiency of the
contacts or effects in the United States, not the comparatively greater
connection between the transaction and some other jurisdiction despite the
sufficiency of the contacts or effects in the United States. See also, Maier,
Extraterritorial Jurisdiction, supra note 4, at 298.
n64. Traditionally, the Supreme Court has weighed territorial
constraints far more heavily in considering the extraterritorial application of
public laws outside the antitrust and securities areas, such as labor law. In
Foley v. Filardo, 336 U.S. 281 (1949), for example, the Court invoked the
"canon of construction which teaches that legislation of Congress, unless
a contrary intent appears, is meant to apply only within the territorial
jurisdiction of the United States," in holding that the federal Eight Hour
Law, (40 U.S.C. 324-25 (1940), which imposes overtime compensation for work in
excess of eight hours a day did not apply to protect a U.S. employee of a U.S.
company abroad. The Supreme Court invoked the same canon more recently to deny
extraterritorial application to Title VII of the Civil Rights Act of 1964, 42
U.S.C. 2000a-2000h-6 (1992). See EEOC v. Arabian American Oil Co., 111 S.Ct.
1227, 1230-35 (1991) (holding that Title VII does not apply to U.S. citizens
employed abroad by U.S. employers). This result has since been overturned by
Congress. See 42 U.S.C. 2000e(f), 12111(4) (1991). These cases sometimes
express a concern that applying U.S. law would interfere unduly with the
regulatory prerogative of foreign nations. See, e.g., Foley v. Filardo, 336
U.S. at 286 ("An intention ... to regulate labor conditions which are the
primary concern of a foreign country should not be attributed to Congress in
the absence of a clearly expressed purpose."). But this generalized
concern works to constrain all extraterritorial applications of the particular
law, not a specific one that constrains a specific application in light of the
comparatively greater regulatory interest of a specific nation. Thus, although
limiting the application of these public laws to the territorial boundaries of
the United States obviously results in greater comity or deference to other
regulatory jurisdictions, the canon of construction itself is no more
comparative or conflicts like than the "conduct" and "intended
effects" tests of extraterritoriality in the antitrust and securities
areas.
n65. See W. Ivor Jennings, The Institutional Theory, in Modern
Theories of Law 68, 72 (1933) ("Public law ... is gradually eating up
private law."); Lowenfeld, Public Law, supra note 2, at 325
("Governments regulate ... more and more activity of all kinds.");
John Henry Merryman, The Public Law-Private Law Distinction in European and
American Law, 17 J. Pub. L. 3, 15 (1968) ("Today it is common for the
state to "intervene' in the society and the economy. The individualistic
state of the 19th century has been replaced by the social state of the 20th
century."); Roscoe Pound, Public Law and Private Law, 24 Cornell L.Q. 469,
470 (1939) [hereinafter Pound, Public Law](discussing "the disappearance
of private law"); Trautman, supra note 4, at 601 (noting "the
increasing scope of public regulation").
n66. See Mary Ann Glendon, The Sources of Law in a Changing Legal
Order, 17 Creighton L. Rev. 663, 666-68 (1984) (discussing "the rise of
statutory law"); Joel P. Trachtman, Conflict of Laws and Accuracy in the
Allocation of Government Responsibility, 26 Vand. J. Transnat'l L. 975, 983
(1994) (noting "the problem of increased statutory and regulatory
law").
n67. See, e.g., Baade, supra note 15, at 435 ("Private law,
too, serves a governmental purpose."); Trachtman, supra note 66, at 997
("Sometimes the public interest is the protection of private
interests."); id. at 1009 ("Provided one accepts as part of public
policy ... the interest in efficiency in private transactions, there is no
longer a preserved sphere for private law."). See also Baade, supra note
15, at 437 (noting that Professor Currie's "government interests
[conflicts] analysis ... has the potential for overcoming the public-private
distinction in the conflict of laws altogether" because "if even
private-law disputes can be resolved by a process which attributes a
governmental purpose to each and every rule of law adopted by a sovereign
state, public-law conflicts can, by definition, be resolved at least as easily
through the application of the same scheme"). Professor Baade concluded
that government interests analysis alone, however, has not resulted in the
abrogation of the public/private distinction because Professor Currie's method
started as a "private-law method in one country and still encounters
resistance even there." But cf., Lowenfeld, Public Law, supra note 2, at
335 ("The governmental interests of which Currie and his followers speak
in the private law contexts are imaginary: governments ... do not really care
about whether the driver of an automobile is liable to a passenger....").
n68. Trachtman, supra note 66, at 985.
n69. Lowenfeld, Public Law, supra note 2, at 325.
n70. Harlow, supra note 3, at 246.
n71. Lowenfeld, Public Law, supra note 2, at 326.
n72. Trautman, supra note 4, at 590.
n73. Maier, Extraterritorial Jurisdiction, supra note 4, at 299.
n74. See Lowenfeld, Public Law, supra note 2, at 367; see
generally Kingman Brewster, Jr., Antitrust and American Business Abroad (1958).
n75. Lowenfeld, Public Law, supra note 2, at 350; see also Lea
Brilmayer, The Extraterritorial Application of American Law: A Methodological
and Constitutional Appraisal, 50 Law & Contemp. Probs. 11 (1987); Larry
Kramer, Vestiges of Beale: Extraterritorial Application of American Law, 1991
Sup. Ct. Rev. 179; Maier, Extraterritorial Jurisdiction, supra note 4, at 287.
n76. I am using comity in this context, as I believe these
commentators use that term, to express essentially a rule of choice of law
reflecting an appropriate concern for the interests and concerns of other
nations in addition to the forum's. See Paul, supra note 28, at 3-4; Maier,
Extraterritorial Jurisdiction, supra note 4, at 318; and Weintraub,
Extraterritorial Application, supra note 52, at 1801.
n77. See United States v. Aluminum Co. of Am., 148 F.2d 416, 443
(1945).
n78. Lowenfeld, Public Law, supra note 2, at 380. Cf., Weinberg,
supra note 43, at 59 ("Words like comity ... have a deceptively right
ring, like good breeding and sweet disposition.").
n79. Trautman, supra note 4, at 586.
n80. Brewster, supra note 74, at 298; see also Kenneth W. Dam,
Extraterritoriality in an Age of Globalization: The Hartford Fire Case, 1993
Sup. Ct. Rev. 289, 324.
n81. See Maier, Extraterritorial Jurisdiction, supra note 4, at
318; see also Lowenfeld, Public Law, supra note 2, at 380.
n82. See, e.g., Lowenfeld, Public Law, supra note 2, at 411
(noting also that this "function... can and should be performed by
judges..."); Paul, supra note 28, at 160 n.335 (citing authorities). Some
of these authors also press the notion that judicial deference to the interests
and laws of other nations will result in greater "reciprocity" by
other nations to the enforcement of U.S. law. See, e.g., Lowenfeld, Public Law,
supra, at 417. But cf. Weinberg, supra note 43, at 54 (questioning this
notion).
n83. Maier, Extraterritorial Jurisdiction, supra note 4, at 319.
See also Friedler, supra note 20, at 503 ("Predictability in international
business transactions is an important state policy that creates a legitimate
state interest."); Trachtman, supra note 66, at 998 ("Predictability
is the type of private value that also should be considered a public value in a
market economy.").
n84. The works urging the application of conflicts principles to
public law employ this assumption. See, e.g., Brewster, supra note 74, at 298;
Lowenfeld, Public Law, supra note 2, at 380; Maier, Extraterritorial
Jurisdiction, supra note 4, at 319; Trautman, supra note 4, at 586; see also,
e.g., Weinberg, supra note 43, at 64 (citing authors who believe that
"facilitation of multistate activity should be a general goal of choice of
law").
n85. Joseph H. Beale, A Treatise on the Conflict of Laws 46
(1935). This concern, of course, is the underlying premise of Professor Beale's
"vested rights" theory of conflicts as applied to private law: each
legal relationship has a single proper "seat" and consequently is
governed only by the law of that state.
n86. Cf. Lauritzen v. Larsen, 345 U.S. 571, 581 (1953) ("The
virtue...of sea-borne commerce lies in its frequent ... contacts with more than
one country. If ... the courts of each were to exploit every such contact to
the limit of its power ... a multiplicity of conflicting and overlapping
burdens would blight international carriage by sea.").
n87. 549 F.2d 597 (9th Cir. 1976).
n88. Turley, supra note 53, at 613.
n89. 549 F.2d at 601.
n90. 549 F.2d at 601, 613. The district court had dismissed the
complaint, reasoning in part that the effect of the alleged conspiracy in the
United States was insufficiently substantial. Id. at 601. The Ninth Circuit
disagreed with this factual conclusion, noting that "the magnitude of the
effect alleged would appear to be sufficient to state a claim," along with
the test of jurisdiction itself. Id. at 615. The Ninth Circuit also held,
contrary to the district court, that Timberlane's complaint was not precluded
by the act of state doctrine. Id. at 608.
n91. Id. at 611-12.
n92. Id. at 613.
n93. See id.
n94. Id. at 614. The Court writes:
Timberlane's other "interest balancing" factors included
the nationality or allegiance of the parties and the locations or principal
places of business or corporations, the extent to which enforcement by either
state can be expected to achieve compliance, ... the extent to which there is
[an] explicit purpose to harm or affect American commerce, the foreseeability
of such effect, and the relative importance to the violations charged of
conduct within the United States as compared with conduct abroad.
Id. The Timberlane factors were very similar to those Professor
Brewster had suggested judges weigh when considering the application of U.S.
antitrust law to international transactions. See Brewster, Antitrust and
American Business Abroad, supra note 74, at 446. On remand, the district court
dismissed the Timberlane complaint (574 F. Supp. 1453 (N.D. Calif. 1983)), and
the Ninth Circuit affirmed, noting a relatively "minimal" effect on
U.S. commerce in comparison to a potentially significant conflict of
jurisdiction with Honduras (749 F.2d 1378, 1386 (9th Cir. 1984)).
n95. 595 F.2d 1287 (3d Cir. 1979).
n96. Id. at 1297.
n97. Specifically, the Court concluded that the district court did
have subject matter jurisdiction over Mannington's claims. See id. at 1292.
Both the Timberlane and Mannington courts considered the issue of the
applicability of U.S. antitrust law to facts alleged to present an issue of
"subject matter jurisdiction" rather than "prescriptive
jurisdiction." See Mannington, 595 F.2d at 292; Timberlane, 549 F.2d at
601. Neither court distinguished the two types of jurisdiction, and both
analyzed the existence of subject matter jurisdiction as if it were a question
of prescriptive or legislative jurisdiction. See, e.g., Mannington, 595 F.2d at
1297. There traditionally are differences between the two types of jurisdiction
(see supra note 41; Restatement (Third) of Foreign Relations 401; see also
Hartford Fire Ins. Co. v. California, 509 U.S. 764, 795 (1993)). However, those
differences are not important to my analysis in light of the courts' treatment
of the issues presented by each as identical (i.e., whether or not a particular
public law applies to a given transaction or issue).
n98. 595 F.2d at 1294 ("Having concluded ... that there is
subject matter jurisdiction, the question remains whether jurisdiction should
be exercised.").
n99. Id. at 1296 ("When foreign nations are involved ... it
is unwise to ignore the fact that foreign policy, reciprocity, comity, and
limitations of judicial power are considerations that should have a bearing on
the decision to exercise or decline jurisdiction.").
n100. Id. at 1297. The Mannington factors differed only slightly
from the Timberlane factors. See supra note 94 and accompanying text.
n101. Id. at 1298 ("We do not believe that the extensive
inquiry required must yield the same answer in each instance.... The individual
interests and policies of each of the foreign nation differ and must be
balanced against our nation's legitimate interest in regulating anticompetitive
activity."). Perhaps it is no surprise that the parties eventually
settled, apparently encouraged in part by the difficulty involved in gathering
and submitting facts sufficient to permit effective balancing of the interests
of each of the other countries against those of the United States. See Harold
G. Maier, Interest Balancing and Extraterritorial Jurisdiction, 31 Am. J. Comp.
L. 579, 589 n.41 (1983).
n102. See, e.g., Uranium Antitrust Litig., Westinghouse Elec. v.
Rio Algom Ltd., 617 F.2d 1248 (7th Cir. 1980); Zenith Radio Corp. v. Matsushita
Elec., 494 F. Supp. 1161 (E.D. Pa. 1980).
n103. Restatement (Third) of Foreign Relations Law 403 (1986)
provides:
403. Limitations on Jurisdiction to Prescribe
(1) Even when one of the bases for jurisdiction under 402 is
present, a state may not exercise jurisdiction to prescribe law with respect to
a person or activity having connections with another state when the exercise of
such jurisdiction is unreasonable.
(2) Whether exercise of jurisdiction over a person or activity is
unreasonable is determined by evaluating all relevant factors, including, where
appropriate:
(a) the link of the activity to the territory of the regulating
state, i.e., the extent to which the activity takes place within the territory,
or has substantial, direct, and foreseeable effect upon or in the territory;
(b) the connections, such as nationality, residence, or economic
activity, between the regulating state and the person principally responsible for
the activity to be regulated, or between that state and those whom the
regulation is designed to protect;
(c) the character of the activity to be regulated, the importance
of regulation to the regulating state, the extent to which other states
regulate such activities, and the degree to which the desirability of such
regulation is generally accepted;
(d) the existence of justified expectations that might be
protected or hurt by the regulation;
(e) the importance of the regulation to the international political,
legal, or economic system; (f) the extent to which the regulation is consistent
with the traditions of the international system;
(g) the extent to which another state may have an interest in
regulating the activity; and
(h) the likelihood of conflict with regulation by another state.
(3) When it would not be unreasonable for each of two states to
exercise jurisdiction over a person or activity, but the prescriptions by the
two states are in conflict, each state has an obligation to evaluate its own as
well as the other state's interest in exercising jurisdiction, in light of all
the relevant factors, Subsection (2); a state should defer to the other state
if that state's interest is clearly greater.
The citation to Timberlane and Mannington actually occurs in note
4 of the Reporter's Notes to section 415 of the Restatement (Third), which
deals expressly with "Jurisdiction to Regulate Anti-Competitive
Activities." However, official Comment (a) to section 415 notes that
"Any exercise of jurisdiction under this section is subject to [section
403's] requirement of reasonableness," and it is clear that Timberlane and
Mannington are cited as examples of judicial applications of the reasonableness
requirement. Section 403's list of factors that must be balanced in assessing
the reasonableness of any given exercise of prescriptive jurisdiction borrows
from the interest balancing factors of section 6 of the Second Restatement of
Conflict of Laws, which was intended to govern choice of law in a private law
context. See, e.g., Maier, Extraterritorial Jurisdiction, supra note 4, at 290
(noting that "the Restatement (Second) of Conflicts is quite explicit that
issues raised by the application of regulatory legislation to foreign events or
persons are primarily the concern of the Restatement (Second) of Foreign
Relations Law").
n104. Restatement (Third) of Foreign Relations Law 403 cmt. a
(1986) ("This section states the principle of reasonableness as a rule of
international law."). It is interesting to note that the Restatement
appears to have departed in this regard from the consensus of the American Law
Institute's membership: "The floor debates preceding the adoption of
section 403(3) by the American Law Institute indicated that an overwhelming majority
agreed that the balancing of state interests in such cases reflected
established principles of comity, not of international law." Paul, supra
note 28, at 46 (citing Harold Maier, Book Review, 83 Am. J. Int'l L. 676, 679
(1989)). Professor Lowenfeld was an Associate Reporter for the Restatement
(Third), and he aptly has been called the "intellectual father" of
section 403. See Harold G. Maier, Resolving Extraterritorial Conflicts, or
"There and Back Again," 25 Va. J. Int'l L. 7, 18 (1984).
n105. Weintraub, Extraterritorial Application, supra note 52, at
1804. See also, Restatement (Third) of Foreign Relations Law 403 cmts. a, e.
n106. See supra note 103 and accompanying text; Maier,
Extraterritorial Jurisdiction, supra note 4, at 300, 294 n.67.
n107. Restatement (Second) of Foreign Relations Law 40 (1965)
provides as follows:
40. Limitations on Exercise of Enforcement Jurisdiction
Where two states have jurisdiction to prescribe and enforce rules
of law and the rules they may prescribe require inconsistent conduct upon the
part of a person, each state is required by international law to consider, in
good faith, moderating the exercise of its enforcement jurisdiction, in the
light of such factors as
(a) vital national interests of each of the states,
(b) the extent and the nature of the hardship that inconsistent
enforcement actions would impose upon the person,
(c) the extent to which the required conduct is to take place in
the territory of the other state,
(d) the nationality of the person, and
(e) the extent to which enforcement by action of either state can
reasonably be expected to achieve compliance with the rule prescribed by that
state.
The change to ab initio judicial interest balancing in section 403
of the Restatement (Third) perhaps reflects Associate Reporter Professor
Lowenfeld's view that judicial interest balancing "should take place
whether or not there is a potential for inconsistent orders." Lowenfeld,
supra note 2, at 401.
n108. Although section 403(3) of the Restatement (Third) seems to
contemplate occasional concurrent jurisdiction even following the interest
balancing assessment dictated by 403(2), section 403(3) urges the avoidance of
concurrent jurisdiction by insisting that, "a state should defer to the
other state if that state's interest is clearly greater." See supra note
103, for the full text of section 403.
n109. See supra note 103 and accompanying text.
n110. See id. at 403(2)(d) (requiring an assessment of the
appropriateness of prescriptive jurisdiction in light of "the existence of
justified expectations that might be protected or hurt by the
regulation"); Lowenfeld, Public Law, supra note 2, at 363 (urging the
assessment of prescriptive jurisdiction on the basis of the "expectations
of the parties" in addition to "governmental interests").
n111. See supra text accompanying note 7.
n112. See Richards v. Lloyd's of London, 135 F.3d 1289, 1291-92
(9th Cir. 1998); Lipcon v. Underwriters at Lloyd's, London, 148 F.3d 1285, 1288
(11th Cir. 1998); Haynsworth v. Lloyd's of London, 121 F.3d 956, 958-60 (5th
Cir. 1997); Allen v. Lloyd's of London, 94 F.3d 923, 926-28 (4th Cir. 1996);
Roby v. Corporation of Lloyd's, 996 F.2d 1353, 1357-58 (2d Cir. 1993); Bonny v.
Society of Lloyd's, 3
F.3d 156, 158-59 (7th Cir. 1993); Riley v. Kingsley Underwriting Agencies,
Ltd., 969 F.2d 953, 955-56 (10th Cir. 1992), for more complete discussions of
the facts in these cases.
n113. See Haynsworth, 121 F.3d at 960; Allen, 94 F.3d at 927.
n114. The Allen plaintiffs made federal securities law fraud and
nondisclosure claims with respect to Lloyd's restructuring plan following its
unanticipated losses, but not with respect to the Names' initial investments in
Lloyd's underwriting syndicates. See Allen, 94 F.3d at 926.
n115. Specifically, the Names relied on dicta in the Supreme
Court's opinions in Mitsubishi Motors Corp. v. Soler Chrysler-Plymouth Inc.,
473 U.S. 614, 637 n.19 (1985), and Vimar Seguros Y Reaseguros, S.A. v. M/V Sky
Reefer, 515 U.S. 528, 541 (1995), that, "In the event [that]
choice-of-forum and choice-of-law clauses operated in tandem as a prospective
waiver of a party's right to pursue statutory remedies for antitrust
violations, we would have little hesitation condemning the agreement as against
public policy." The Names also relied on explicit antiwaiver provisions in
the Securities Acts declaring void "any ... stipulation ... binding any
person acquiring any security to waive compliance" with any rights secured
or rules imposed by the federal securities laws. See 15 U.S.C. 77n for the
nonwaiver provision of the Securities Act of 1933, and 15 U.S.C. 78c(a) for the
nonwaiver provision of the Securities and Exchange Act of 1934.
n116. See Rodriguez de Quijas v. Shearson/American Express, Inc.,
490 U.S. 477 (1989); Shearson/American Express, Inc. v. McMahon, 482 U.S. 220
(1987); Scherk v. Alberto-Culver Co., 417 U.S. 506 (1974); see also Gilmer v.
Interstate/Johnson Lane Corp., 500 U.S. 20, at 26 (1991) (noting that "it
is by now clear that statutory claims may be the subject of an arbitration
agreement...").
n117. The choice of forum clauses in the agreements signed by the
Names had changed over time, with pre-1986 investors in Lloyd's agreeing to
submit any disputes to arbitration in London, and post-1986 investors agreeing to
submit any disputes to London courts. See Haynsworth v. Lloyd's of London, 121
F.3d at 959-60. Because English conflict of law rules honor the traditional
public law taboo, English courts necessarily would not entertain claims based
on U.S. securities law. See, e.g., Roby v. Corp. of Lloyd's, 996 F.2d at 1362
("English conflict of law rules do not permit recognition of foreign tort
or statutory law."). The Lloyd's courts assumed the same to be true of
English arbitrators. Id. Although the Supreme Court's decisions in Scherck,
Mitsubishi, and Vimar Seguros would have countenanced a change of forum in the
Lloyd's cases that did not involve the displacement of U.S. public law, those
cases are not precedent for a change of forum resulting in the displacement of
U.S. public law.
n118. The Lloyd's courts all relied on The Bremen v. Zapata
Offshore Co., 407 U.S. 1 (1972), and Carnival Cruise Lines, Inc. v. Shute, 499
U.S. 585 (1991), both of which involved the enforcement of choice of forum and
choice of law clauses in the context of contract and tort claims in a maritime
context: The Bremen concerned negligent towage, and Carnival Cruise Lines,
negligent passenger carriage. See Richards v. Lloyd's of London, 135 F.3d 1289,
1293-94; Lipcon v. Underwriters at Lloyd's, London, 148 F.3d 1285, 1291-92;
Haynsworth, 121 F.3d at 961-65; Roby v. Corp. of Lloyd's, 996 F.2d at 1363;
Bonny v. Society of Lloyd's, 3 F.3d 156, 160.
n119. See Carnival Cruise Lines, Inc. v. Shute, 499 U.S. at 595
(1991); The Bremen v. Zapata, 407 U.S. at 12-14 (1972). In Roby, 996 F.2d at
1363, the Second Circuit remarked:
The Supreme Court has [determined that] forum selection and choice
of law clauses are "unreasonable" [only] (1) if their incorporation
into the agreement was the result of fraud or overreaching ... (2) if the
complaining party "will for all practical purposes be deprived of his day
in court, due to the grave inconvenience or unfairness of the selected forum
... (3) if the fundamental unfairness of the chosen law may deprive plaintiff
of a remedy ... or (4) if the clauses contravene a strong public policy ....
n120. See, e.g., Riley, 969 F.2d at 957 n.4 ("We need not
decide whether Riley's participation as a Name constitutes a security, or
whether Lloyd's or the Defendant Underwriters are subject to the provisions of
the 1933 or 1934 Securities Act."); Accord Haynsworth, 121 F.3d at 966;
Roby, 996 F.2d at 1357; Bonny, 3 F.3d at 160 (implicit). Allen decides some
applicability issues adversely to the defendants, but in a settlement context.
See Allen, 94 F.3d at 930-31.
n121. See supra note 103 for the text of section 403.
n122. See, e.g., Lipcon, 148 F.3d at 1294-95("To conclude
that the anti-waiver provisions of the United States securities laws
categorically preclude sophisticated parties from entering into international
agreements [selecting a single applicable law] ... would undermine
[predictability and international comity]."); Roby, 996 F.2d at 1360
("It defies reason to suggest that a plaintiff may circumvent [choice]
clauses merely by stating claims under laws not recognized by the forum
selected in the agreement."); Allen, 94 F.3d at 931 ("In summary, the
policies of the United States securities laws do not override the parties'
choice of forum and law for resolving disputes in this case."); id. at 930
("To permit the Names to escape their agreements to be bound by the laws
and rules of the British market just at a time when they face losses would also
violate the most fundamental precepts of international comity.").
n123. See, e.g., Allen, 94 F.3d at 929 ("We do not believe
that enforcing the parties' forum selection and choice of law provisions in
this case will subvert the United States Securities laws' policy of prohibiting
fraud. British law not only prohibits fraud and misrepresentations ... but also
affords Names adequate remedies in the United Kingdom."); Bonny, 3 F.3d at
161 ("We are satisfied that several remedies in England [will] vindicate
plaintiffs' substantive rights while not subverting the United States policies
of insuring full and fair disclosure by issuers and deterring the exploitation
of United States investors."); Riley, 996 F.2d at 1365 ("We are
satisfied ... that the Roby Names have several adequate remedies in England to
vindicate their substantive rights....").
n124. See, e.g., Lipcon, 148 F.3d 1285; Haynsworth, 121 F.3d at
969 ("The American system of securities law may be the broadest, most
comprehensive of all. We refuse to accept the notion, however, that the sheer
scope of U.S. securities law automatically renders that of other countries
inferior...."); Allen, 94 F.3d at 929-30 ("The United States nexus to
the transactions is ... incidental.... [A] court may abstain from exercising
enforcement jurisdiction when the extraterritorial effect of a particular
remedy is so disproportionate to harm within the United States as to offend
principles of comity."); Roby, 996 F.2d at 1364 ("Lloyd's is a
British concern which raises capital in over 80 countries. Its operations are
clearly international in scope.... Comity...weighs in favor of enforcing the
[choice] clauses."); Bonny, 3 F.3d at 159 n.9 ("Lloyd's [is] a
distinctively British entity....").
n125. See CLACO, supra note 17, art. 7(1). A number of contracting
states, including, importantly, Germany and the United Kingdom, have reserved
the right to exclude this provision. See Whincop & Keyes, supra note 28, at
522.
n126. Bundesgesetz <um u>ber das Internationale Privatrecht,
art. 13., SR (Switz. 1988), as translated in Baade, supra note 15, at 462.
n127. See supra note 32 for the relevant portion of section 187
(2)(b).
n128. See the concluding sentence of supra note 103 and the
quotation from Maier.
n129. See Baade, supra note 15, at 466-72, 481, 495.
n130. See supra note 116 for a sampling of such rulings.
n131. See, e.g., Mitsubishi Motors Corp. v. Soler
Chrysler-Plymouth Inc., 473 U.S. at 638 (1986).
n132. Cf. Restatement (Third) of Foreign Relations Law 483 (1986)
(regarding the recognition and enforcement of certain foreign public law judgments
(specifically, tax and penalty judgments), wherein the first Reporter's comment
notes that "no rule of United States law or of international law would be
violated if a court of the United States enforced [such] a judgment of a
foreign court....").
n133. See supra note 101 and accompanying text.
n134. See, e.g., Dodge, supra note 25, at 101; Paul, supra note
28, at 1; Weinberg, supra note 43, at 53.
n135. Weinberg, supra note 43, at 61.
n136. See Paul, supra note 28, at 71 ("By allowing transnational
business to choose legal systems imposing a lower regulatory burden than the
United States, U.S. courts have effectively lowered regulatory
standards."); Weinberg, supra note 43, at 71 ("Systematic denials of
law enforcement must pro tanto encourage predatory or injurious
conduct."); id. at 72 (noting the increased "magnitude of the risk of
a reciprocal posture of nonenforcement of forum law"); id. at 60 ("If
the forum refuses to take unilateral responsibility for law enforcement, there
is a finite risk of system-wide failure to govern injurious behavior.").
n137. The displacement of forum private law likely does not have
significant regulatory consequences, even though a defendant's motive in
seeking displacement might be similar personal advantage. See e.g., Weintraub,
Extraterritorial Application, supra note 52, at 1818 ("The sovereign's
interest in enforcing its regulatory rules is of a different order than the
"interest,' meaning the social policy, underlying the rules of torts and
contracts."); Lowenfeld, Public Law, supra note 2, at 335
("Governmental interests ... in the private law contexts are nearly all
imaginary: governments ... do not really care about whether the driver of an
automobile is liable to a passenger."). According to one source:
A government always has a direct interest in the outcome of a
regulatory case, even when the governmental viewpoint is represented by a
citizen-prosecutor seeking private recovery .... In this sense, they are
distinguishable from nonregulatory choice-of-law cases in which the issue is
which of two or more conflicting governmental policies shall be applied to
private persons, none of whom functionally serves as a government surrogate.
Maier, Extraterritorial Jurisdiction, supra note 4, at 289.
n138. See supra text accompanying notes 76-82.
n139. See supra text accompanying notes 83-86; see also, Laker
Airways Ltd. v. Sabena, Belgian World Airways, 731 F.2d 909, 952 (D.C. Cir.
1984) ("There is ... no rule of international law holding that a
"more reasonable' assertion of jurisdiction mandatorily displaces a
"less reasonable' assertion of jurisdiction as long as both are, in fact,
consistent with the limitations on jurisdiction imposed by international
law"). Obviously, singular regulation presumably is better for commerce
than multiple regulation in cases in which the differing regulations actually
require impossibly inconsistent conduct on the part of the same individual or
company, but that is not a condition of interest balancing among those who advocate
the merger of conflicts principles with rules governing the application of
public law. See, e.g., Lowenfeld, Public Law, supra note 2, at 401 (urging that
interest balancing "take place whether or not there is a potential for
inconsistent orders").
n140. See Roscoe Pound, Liberty of Contract, 18 Yale L.J. 454
(1909), (discussing these cases and the jurisprudence on which they were
based).
n141. 731 F.2d 909 (D.C. Cir. 1984).
n142. Id. at 949. See also, Mannington Mills Inc. v. Congoleum
Corp., 595 F.2d 1287, 1299 (3rd Cir. 1979) (Adams, J., concurring and
dissenting in part) ("I do not agree that a court may conclude that it is
invested with subject-matter jurisdiction under the Sherman Act but may
nonetheless abstain from exercising such jurisdiction in deference to
considerations of international comity."); G. Chesire & P. North,
Private International Law 4 (12th ed. 1992) ("The word itself is
incompatible with the judicial function, for comity is a matter for sovereigns,
not for judges ...."); Paul, supra note 28, at 72 ("Allowing
transnational business in effect to opt out of higher regulatory burdens raises
... an institutional competence issue regarding whether the decision ostensibly
to relax regulatory standards should be made by the courts, or whether it
should be left to the legislature."); EEOC v. Arabian American Oil Co.,
499 U.S. 244, 259 (1991) (noting that if Congress wished Title VII to apply to
U.S. citizens employed abroad by U.S. companies, Congress could "amend
Title VII and in doing so ... calibrate its provisions in a way we
cannot").
n143. Trautman, supra note 4, at 621.
n144. See supra note 101 and accompanying text.
n145. Laker Airways, 731 F.2d at 950 (noting the procedural and
discovery difficulties that would occur in an interest balancing analysis);
Zoelsch v. Arthur Andersen & Co., 824 F.2d 27, 32 n.2 (D.C. Cir. 1987)
("It would ... seem counterproductive [in deciding the jurisdictional
reach of the antifraud provisions of the Securities Act] to adopt a balancing
test, or any test that makes jurisdiction turn on a welter of specific
facts.").
n146. Weintraub, Extraterritorial Application, supra note 52, at
1817; see also Maier, Extraterritorial Jurisdiction, supra note 4, at 297-98,
310; Dodge, supra note 25, at 163-65 (collecting examples of politically
negotiated resolutions of prescriptive jurisdictional conflicts).
n147. See Weintraub, Extraterritorial Application, supra note 52,
at 1817.
n148. Obviously, the "conduct or intended effects" test
of prescriptive jurisdiction converges somewhat with the "minimum
contacts" test of in personam jurisdiction. The focus of both tests on the
"sufficiency" of contacts in an absolute sense (as opposed to their
"comparative sufficiency," as with interest balancing) is a virtue for
planners of international business in terms of being able to identify and
factor into transactions, ex ante, the cost of compliance (or, the cost of
avoiding business in any particular jurisdiction).
n149. Kaczmarek v. Allied Chemical Corp., 836 F.2d 1055, 1057 (7th
Cir. 1987). Judge Easterbrook comments that he "would be most reluctant to
accept an approach that calls on the district judge to throw a heap of factors
on a table and then slice and dice to taste." Reinsurance Co. of Am. v. Administratia
Asigurarilor de Stat, 902 F.2d 1275, 1283 (7th Cir. 1990)
n150. Lowenfeld, Public Law, supra note 2, at 311.
n151. See discussion supra Part IV.A.
n152. See, e.g., McConnaughay, The Risks and Virtues of
Lawlessness, 93 Nw. U. L. Rev. (forthcoming Apr. 1999). This issue also would
have implications for the enforceability in the forum that supplied the public
law of any judgment rendered pursuant to the law in the substitute forum.
n153. Obviously, even if there were a general rule in favor of
judicial recognition and application of foreign public law the recognizing
forum still could decline to apply foreign public law if doing so would
contravene an important policy of the recognizing forum. See supra notes 30-36;
infra note 257, and accompanying text.
n154. Hartford Fire Ins. Co. v. California, 509 U.S. 764 (1993).
n155. 509 U.S. at 77 n.24, 798. While the Court saw "no need
to address [the] contention here" that "comity concerns figure into
the ... analysis [of] whether jurisdiction exists [ab initio] under the Sherman
Act" because "the parties conceded jurisdiction at oral
argument," it did say that:
This contention is inconsistent with the general understanding
that the Sherman Act covers foreign conduct producing a substantial intended
effect in the United States, and that concerns of comity come into play, if at
all, only after a court has determined that the acts complained of are subject
to Sherman Act jurisdiction.
Id. at 797 n.24 (1993).
Moreover, the Court's actual holding seems to be that comity is
not a consideration in the exercise of public law jurisdiction until a
"true conflict" exists between the U.S. law and a foreign law, which,
as the Court defined "true conflict," would preclude judicial
considerations of comity prior to determining the jurisdictional reach of the
U.S. law. See infra text accompanying notes 163-164.
n156. 345 U.S. 571 (1953).
n157. 358 U.S. 354 (1959).
n158. 46 U.S.C.A. 688 (West 1998). The Jones Act allows injured
seamen to maintain damages actions in U.S. courts.
n159. See Hartford Fire, 509 U.S. at 795.
n160. The majority found the following statement made by the
London reinsurers at oral argument to be a concession: "Our position is
not that the Sherman Act does not apply.... Our position is that there are
certain circumstances, and that this is one of them, in which the interests of
another State are sufficient that the exercise of that jurisdiction should be
restrained." Id. The Hartford Fire dissent disagreed about whether the
London reinsurers actually had intended this as a concession, but the substance
of the disagreement seemed to have less to do with the interpretation of the
London reinsurers' remarks than it did with the legal issue of whether or not
comity or comparative interest balancing is relevant to the jurisdictional
reach of the Sherman Act. Significantly, despite viewing the defendants'
statement as a concession, the Hartford Fire majority clearly endorsed the
Alcoa "intended effects" test as the test of the jurisdictional reach
of the Sherman Act. Id. ("It is well established by now that the Sherman
Act applies to foreign conduct that was meant to produce and did in fact
produce some substantial effect in the United States.").
n161. See 509 U.S. at 779, n.9, 797. There was a significant
disagreement between the Hartford Fire majority and dissent about whether
"subject matter jurisdiction" or "prescriptive
jurisdiction" was at issue in the case, with the majority arguing subject
matter, and the dissent, prescriptive. Id at 796 n.22, 813-14. Although that
nomenclature issue is important, it largely masks the underlying issue of
substance that both the majority and dissent addressed and which is the chief
concern of this Article: namely, whether or not a court should conduct a
conflicts analysis (i.e., consider international comity and comparative
interest balancing) in conjunction with determining the jurisdictional reach of
a public law. The nomenclature issue becomes important if one views section 403
of the Restatement (Third) of Foreign Relations Law (supra note 103) as
supplying the rule of decision on the underlying question of substance, for
section 403, which by its terms applies to prescriptive jurisdiction rather
than subject matter jurisdiction, insists on comparative interest balancing
prior to determining the jurisdictional reach of public law. The dissent
mistakenly viewed section 403 as accurately reflecting international law and
therefore as supplying the rule of decision. See infra text accompanying notes
196 for a discussion of the dissent's position. Because the majority correctly
did not view section 403 as supplying the rule of decision, it thus could have
conceded the nomenclature issue and still decided the substantive issue the way
it did (i.e., that comparative interest balancing is not a permissible
constraint on the jurisdictional reach of the Sherman Act, at least in the
absence of a "true conflict"). One commentator has stated that
"there is no such general practice and hence no customary international
law like that advanced in section 403." Phillip Trimble, The Supreme Court
and International Law: The Demise of Restatement Section 403, 89 Am. J. Int'l
L. 53, 55 (1995).
n162. 509 U.S. at 798.
n163. Id. at 799, citing Restatement (Third) of Foreign Relations
law 403 cmt. e (1986). Section 403 is reprinted in supra note 103.
n164. 509 U.S. at 799.
n165. See supra note 155 and accompanying text.
n166. 509 U.S. at 812-22.
n167. See supra text accompanying notes 87-101.
n168. See supra text accompanying note 155.
n169. See supra text accompanying notes 106-108.
n170. See supra note 107 for the text of section 40.
n171. See supra text accompanying notes 106-107.
n172. 509 U.S. at 796-97.
n173. The "true conflict" hurdle is so high, in fact,
that one would expect it (1) to occur only rarely (e.g., when participants in
international transactions have been so ill advised that they actually have
encountered a "true conflict" unbeknownst) and (2) probably to
overlap with the foreign compulsion defense when it does occur. See Restatement
(Third) of Foreign Relations Law 441-44 (1985). "True conflicts" as
presented in Hartford Fire and section 40 of course are very different from
traditional "true conflicts" in the context of private law conflicts.
"True conflicts" exist in a private law context whenever differing
state laws apply to the same issue. See, e.g., Lowenfeld, Public Law, supra
note 2, at 398; Weinberg, supra note 43, at 57-59; Weintraub, Extraterritorial
Application, supra note 52, at 1804; Hartford Fire, 509 U.S. at 820-21 (Scalia,
J., dissenting). Although differing outcomes of a dispute might result in a
private law context involving a "true conflict," inconsistent conduct
rarely would be required because private law seldom is regulatory in that sense.
See, e.g., Weinberg, supra note 43, at 59 n.28.
n174. 509 U.S. at 815-19.
n175. See id. at 820-21.
n176. 345 U.S. 571 (1953).
n177. 358 U.S. 354 (1959).
n178. See Hartford Fire, 509 U.S. at 815-16.
n179. See, e.g., Romero v. International Terminal Operating Co.,
358 U.S. at 383.
n180. See id. at 383-84.
n181. Lauritzen v. Larsen, 345 U.S. at 582.
n182. Romero v. International Terminal Operating Co., 358 U.S. at
382-83.
n183. See Romero, 358 U.S. at 384; Lauritzen, 345 U.S. at 592. The
Jones Act since has been amended to more clearly delineate its jurisdictional
reach by restricting its availability to U.S. seamen in certain circumstances.
See 46 U.S.C. 688(b) (1994).
n184. 509 U.S. at 815-17.
n185. Trautman, supra note 4, at 588. Later commentators also make
this assumption about Lauritzen and Romero. See, e.g., Maier, Extraterritorial
Jurisdiction, supra note 4, at 303 (suggesting that Lauritzen and Romero reveal
the "functional intersection" of public law and conflict of laws in
"transnational regulatory cases"). See also, e.g., Timberlane Lumber
Co. v. Bank of Am., 549 F.2d 597, 614 (9th Cir. 1976); Restatement (Third) of
Foreign Relations Law 403 and reporter's notes (1986).
n186. See discussion infra Part VI, and particularly the text
accompanying notes 213-220, for a discussion of those aspects of a law that
distinguish a private law statute from a public law statute.
n187. Both the Lauritzen and Romero Courts acknowledge this
explicitly. See Lauritzen, 345 U.S. at 583 ("We therefore review the several
factors which, alone or in combination, are generally conceded to influence
choice of law to govern a tort claim...."); Romero, 358 U.S. at 382
("The similarity in purpose and function of the Jones Act and the general
maritime principles of compensation for personal injury, admit of no rational
differentiation of treatment for choice of law purposes.").
n188. See supra text accompanying note 15.
n189. See discussion infra notes 236-239. Of course, commentators
today recognize that tort law has a regulatory effect, if not purpose, and that
regulatory law, like the Sherman Antitrust Act, is tortlike in many respects.
Part VI discusses how those similarities might bear on the question of
distinguishing laws or provisions of laws whose applicability should not be
subject to judicial comparative interest balancing (i.e., whose applicability
is within the public law taboo), from those whose applicability should turn on
comparative interest balancing. For present purposes, it is important to keep
in mind that, contrary to the suggestions of proponents of the merger of public
law and conflict of laws principles, the similarities between tort law and
antitrust law suggest more that tort law should be considered
"public" than that antitrust law should be considered
"private."
n190. Cf. Trautman, supra note 4, at 618 (noting that Lauritzen
"may [simply] demonstrate that courts are probably most likely to
entertain an argument that respect should be given foreign law in cases in
which the primary purpose of the federal statute is to extend or clarify
private rights, as in the Jones Act").
n191. Or more precisely, that Hartford Fire signals a revival of
that prong of the public law taboo that forbids the displacement by judicial
comparative interest balancing of otherwise applicable forum public law.
Hartford Fire says nothing about the prong of the taboo concerning the
recognition by a forum of foreign public law. In fact, Hartford Fire to a large
extent is but an echo of the 1988 decision by the European Court of Justice in
the Wood Pulp Cases. Case 89/85, In re Joined Cases "wood pulp' v.
Commission, 1988 E.C.R. 5193. In those cases, the European Court essentially
applied an Alcoa "intended effects" test to apply European Community
competition law to a cartel (including several American firms) of foreign
producers of wood pulp that had fixed the price of wood pulp imported into the
EEC. Significantly, the European Court held that international comity was
irrelevant to its determination of jurisdiction under the intended effects
test. See id. at 5244 para. 22. The court held that there was no need to
consider comparative interest balancing further because "there is not ...
any contradiction between the conduct required by the United States and that
required by the Community since the [U.S.] Webb Pomerene Act merely exempts the
conclusion of export cartels from the application of anti-trust laws but does
not require such cartels to be concluded." Id. at 5244 para. 20. In other
words, the European Court of Justice held that judicial comparative interest
balancing is not appropriate in determining the jurisdictional reach of public
law in the absence of a "true conflict."
n192. See discussion infra Part VI. See also supra text
accompanying notes 65-71.
n193. See McConnaughay, supra note 152, for a discussion of the
implications of Hartford Fire for the Lloyd's cases.
n194. Great Britain's insurance regulatory scheme is described in
some detail in the district court's opinion in Hartford Fire Ins. Co. v.
California, 723 F. Supp. 464 (N.D. Cal. 1989), in Lipcon v. Underwriters at
Lloyd's of London, 148 F.3d 1285, 1288 (11th Cir. 1998), and in Haynsworth v.
Lloyd's of London, 121 F.3d 956, 958-60 (5th Cir. 1997).
n195. In Hartford Fire, British law appeared to permit the concerted
activity by London reinsurers that U.S. law would forbid, and in the Lloyd's
cases British law appeared not to require the same degree of disclosure in the
sale of securities as is required by U.S. law.
n196. The Hartford Fire defendants conceded the applicability of
the Sherman Act to their conduct. See 509 U.S. at 795 and supra note 160 and
accompanying text. In contrast, the Lloyd's courts essentially assumed the
applicability of the Securities Acts to the U.S. Investments in Lloyd's syndicates
for purposes of deciding those cases. See supra text accompanying note 120.
n197. See, e.g., Hartford Fire, 509 U.S. at 819, and supra note
124, with respect to the Lloyd's cases.
n198. See 15 U.S.C. 77n for the antiwaiver provision of the
Securities Act of 1933 and 15 U.S.C. 78cc(a) for the antiwaiver provision of
the Securities and Exchange Act of 1934, both declaring void "any,
condition, stipulation, or provision binding any person ... to waive
compliance" with any of the rights secured or rules imposed by the federal
securities laws.
n199. See, e.g., Lipcon, 148 F.3d at 1288; Allen v. Lloyd's of
London, 94 F.3d 923, 929 (4th Cir. 1996) ("We do not believe that
enforcing the parties' forum selection and choice of law provisions in this
case will subvert the United States securities laws' policy of prohibiting
fraud. British law not only prohibits fraud and misrepresentation ... but also
affords Names adequate remedies in the United Kingdom."); Bonny v. Society
of Lloyd's, 3 F.3d 156,
161 (7th Cir. 1993) ("We are satisfied that several remedies in England
will vindicate plaintiffs' substantive rights while not subverting the United
States' policies of insuring full and fair disclosure by issuers and deterring
the exploitation of United States investors."); Roby v. Corp. of Lloyd's,
96 F.2d 1353, 1365 (2nd Cir. 1993) ("We are satisfied ... that the Roby
Names have several adequate remedies in England to vindicate their substantive
rights ....").
n200. See, e.g., Roby, 996 F.2d at 1364 ("Lloyd's is a British
concern which raises capital in over 80 nations.... Comity ... weighs in favor
of enforcing the [choice] clauses."); Allen, 94 F.3d at 929-30 ("The
United States nexus to the transaction ... is thus incidental.... "[A]
court may abstain from exercising enforcement jurisdiction when the
extraterritorial effect of a particular remedy is so disproportionate to harm
within the United States as to offend principles of comity.'")(quoting
Consolidated Gold Fields PLC v. Minorco, S.A.; 871 F.2d 252, 263 (2nd Cir.
1989)); Bonny, 3 F.3d at 159 n.9 ("Lloyd's [is] a distinctively British
entity...."); id. at 162 ("The fact that an international transaction
may be subject to laws and remedies that are different or less favorable than
those of the United States is not alone a valid basis to deny enforcement of
... choice of law clauses."); Lipcon, 148 F.3d at 1295 (concluding that
enforcement of the parties' choice of law clauses would undermine international
comity).
n201. The Lloyd's courts' displacement analysis fails because of
the Supreme Court's holding in Knott v. Botany Mills, 179 U.S. 69, 71 (1900),
which nullified a contractual choice of law clause that would have displaced
mandatory provisions of the U.S. Harter Act. See 46 U.S.C. 190-195 (a public
law imposing certain duties on common carriers by land or sea). The
displacement argument also ignores key dicta in the Supreme Court's decisions
of Vimar Seguros Y. Reaseguros, S.A.v. M/V Sky Reefer, 515 U.S. 528, 540 (1995)
(indicating that in the event that "choice-of-forum and choice-of-law
clauses operated in tandem as a prospective waiver of a party's right to pursue
statutory remedies for antitrust violations, we would have little hesitation
condemning the agreement as against public policy"). See also Mitsubishi
Motors Corp. v. Soler Chrysler-Plymouth Inc., 473 U.S. 614, n.19 at 637 (1985).
However, the results themselves in the Lloyd's cases are not necessarily
inappropriate. It is entirely possible on the facts of those cases that the
"conduct or intended effects" jurisdictional threshold of the
Securities Acts may not have been met. See McConnaughay, supra note 152.
n202. See discussion supra Part IV.A.
n203. See discussion supra Part IV.C.
n204. See discussion supra Part IV.B. Forbidding judicial comparative
interest balancing as a constraint on the jurisdictional reach of otherwise
applicable forum public law does not mean that the jurisdictional reach of
public law is unconstrained. It means simply that other branches of government
must be more diligent in their efforts to consider foreign interests when
prescribing or enforcing public law. There are numerous examples that this is
precisely what occurs. See, e.g., Foreign Trade Antitrust Improvements Act, 15
U.S.C. 6(a)(1)(1982) (requiring that international export trade have a
"direct, substantial, and reasonably foreseeable effect" on U.S.
commerce before it will violate the Sherman Act); Regulation S, Securities Act
of 1933, 17 C.F.R. 230.901-.904 (1991) (removing the 1933 Act's registration
requirement for offers and sales of securities that occur outside the United
States); U.S. Dep't of Justice, Antitrust Guide for International Operations,
Antitrust Div. (1977); see also Lowenfeld, Public Law, supra note 2, at 364
("It is a mistake to assume that a statute cannot be drafted ... that
adopts a reasoned weighing of relevant considerations rather than maximum reach
as the standard for exercise of legislative jurisdiction.").
n205. See supra text accompanying notes 65-71.
n206. Merryman, supra note 65, at 17.
n207. Paul, supra note 28, at 35.
n208. David Jackson, Mandatory Rules and Rules of "ordre
public,' in Contract Conflicts 59, 64 (P.M. North ed., 1982).
n209. These limitations include conduct or effects within the
sovereign territory or the nationality of the actor. See supra note 54.
"Public law" and "private law" in this Article, of course,
refer to public domestic law and private domestic law, not to public
international law or private international law. The differences are important.
Public international law essentially regulates relations among nations (and
sometimes relations between nations and individuals, as in the area of human
rights); private international law is a synonym for conflict of laws. See,
e.g., Paul, supra note 28, at 2 n.1; Baade, supra note 15, at 447. As I discuss
in Subpart VI.A, private domestic law, such as contracts and torts, concerns
relations between individuals within a given jurisdiction; public domestic law,
such as antitrust or securities law, tends to be more concerned with relations
between individuals and society, or with relations between individuals insofar
as they significantly affect the public interest.
n210. See Merryman, supra note 65, at 19 ("Conceptions of
public law and private law have never figured greatly in the history of the
common law."); Jackson, supra note 208, at 59 ("The [public law]
label is used in the United Kingdom to describe that category of rules
concerned with [the] state as distinct from individual interest but no legal
consequence flows from the categorisation.").
n211. See generally, Symposium, The Public/Private Distinction,
130 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1289 (1982); Robert H. Mnookin, The Public/Private
Dichotomy: Political Disagreement and Academic Repudiation, 130 U. Pa. L. Rev.
1429 (1982).
n212. The phrase "all law is public law" is Lenin's.
Letter from V. Lenin to Kurskii, 1922, in 20 Soviet Legal Philosophy 292 (H.
Babb trans., 20th Century Legal Philosophy Series No. 5, 1951), cited in
Merryman, supra note 65, at 13 n.36.
n213. Pound, Public Law, supra note 65, at 470.
n214. Merryman, supra note 65, at 11.
n215. Maier, Extraterritorial Jurisdiction, supra note 4, at 289;
see also Lowenfeld, Public Law, supra note 2, at 335 ("Governments (as
contrasted with courts) do not really care about whether the driver of an
automobile is liable to the passenger in the case of an accident.").
n216. Id. One traditional distinction between public law and
private law was that public law causes of action were usually brought by
government authorities, private law actions by aggrieved private individuals.
See Randy E. Barnett, Foreword: Four Senses of the Public Law-Private Law
Distinction, 9 Harv. J.L. & Pub. Pol'y 267, 269 (1994); L. Harold Levinson,
The Public Law/Private Law Distinction in the Courts, 57 Geo. Wash. L. Rev.
1579, 1580 (1989). As Professor Maier's quote in the text accompanying note 215
indicates, it is now generally accepted that public law can afford private
remedies and remain public law. See also Lowenfeld, Public Law, supra note 2,
at 350.
n217. Merryman, supra note 65, at 12. It was the heightened
interest of the sovereign that accounted for that prong of the public law taboo
that forbade forum recognition of foreign public law. See supra note 24 and
accompanying text. Cf. Restatement (First) of Conflict of Laws 610 (1934)
("No action can be maintained on a right created by the law of a foreign
state as a method of furthering its own governmental interests.").
n218. See Barnett, supra note 216, at 268; see also Jeffrie G.
Murphy & Jules L. Coleman, The Philosophy of Law: An Introduction to
Jurisprudence 145 (1984) ("The standard way of drawing [this distinction]
is to say that duties imposed by tort law cover private harms, and those
imposed in the criminal law cover public harms.").
n219. See, e.g., sources cited supra note 66. Cf. Jackson, supra
note 208, at 61 ("There is sometimes a tendency to see a distinction
between a statutory and a judge made domestic rule when considering whether
they are subject to or over-ride the conflicts process - to assume that a
statutory provision is more likely to over-ride it.").
n220. As one California statute notes, "statutes are public
or private." Cal. Civ. Proc. Code 1898 (Deering 1997).
n221. See, e.g., Barnett, supra note 216, at 273-74.
n222. See, e.g., Trachtman, supra note 66, at 1010.
n223. See, e.g., Weinberg, supra note 43, at 67, 70. The fact that
government interest analysis represents the dominant approach to torts conflict
of laws would seem to reflect this proposition as well. See Bauerfeld, Note,
Effectiveness of Choice-of-Law Clauses, supra note 32, at 1685 ("Often,
too, regulatory schemes are partially effected through contract law.").
n224. Allan Philip, Mandatory Rules, Public Law (Political Rules)
and Choice of Law in the E.E.C. Convention on the Law Applicable to Contractual
Obligations, in Contract Conflicts (P.M. North ed. 1982).
n225. See Pound, Public Law, supra note 65, at 474; Barnett, supra
note 216, at 268.
n226. See Pound, Public Law, supra note 65, at 471-72. The maxim
jus publicum privatorum pactis mutari non potest expresses "the
preeminence of public over private concerns." Baade, supra note 15, at
432.
n227. See, e.g., Weintraub, Extraterritorial Jurisdiction, supra
note 52, at 1806 and passim (using "regulatory legislation");
Friedler, supra note 20, at 516 n.231 (equating the traditional French public
law category of lois de police with "certain French regulatory
laws"); Philip, supra note 224, at 88 ("Public laws are akin to what
is sometimes called political laws and in French "lois de police.'");
Baade, supra note 15, at 466 (noting that currency controls, while not
"fiscal," "revenue," or "penal," "obviously
[are] regulatory, and readily classified as pertaining to public law according
to traditional notions"); Lowenfeld, Public Law, supra note 2, at 325;
Trautman, supra note 4, at 601. Public law, of course, also can refer to
constitutional, criminal, and revenue laws, and to administrative law governing
the operations of government. See, e.g., Baade, supra note 15, at 447.
n228. See Jackson, supra note 208, at 89; Baade, supra note 15, at
447. Professor Baade suggests four categories or "strata" of public
law: (1) constitutional and administrative law, which governs the "organs
of government," (2) penal and revenue law, which reflect each nation's
territorial monopoly of coercive power, (3) national economic and service
institutions, which concern the monetary system and the management of public
property, and (4) regulatory law, which "operates indirectly by
channeling, penalizing, invalidating, or rewarding conduct between private
parties." Id. This paper, of course, is concerned with Professor Baade's
last category.
n229. A.J.E. Jaffey, Choice of Law in Relation to Ius Dispositivum
with Particular Reference to the E.E.C. Convention on the Law Applicable to
Contractual Obligations, in Contract Conflicts 33, 41 (P.M. North ed. 1982).
n230. This is the definition of mandatory law provided by the
European Community's Convention on the Law Applicable to Contractual
Obligations, supra note 17, arts. 3(3), 7.
n231. Michael Pryles, Reflections on the E.E.C. Contractual
Obligations Convention - An Australian Perspective, in Contract Conflicts, 323,
331 (P.M. North, ed. 1982); see also Arthur von Mehren, A General View of
Contract, 7 International Encyclopedia of Comparative Law 3, 6 (1982)
("Transactions to which public law rules apply are not by that token to be
considered as outside the domain of contract, broadly conceived. However,
although contractual in the sense that a significant element of autonomous
ordering is present, such transactions are in many respects regulated by
special rules.").
n232. Jaffey, supra note 229, at 40; see also Philip, supra note
224, at 83 ("Mandatory rules are rules which have the purpose of
protecting one or both parties or a third party.").
n233. Baade, supra note 15, at 472; see also Giuliano &
Lagarde, supra note 29, at 28 (describing mandatory rules as "notably
rules on cartels, competition and restrictive practices, consumer protection
and certain rules concerning carriage").
n234. Philip, supra note 224, at 83.
n235. See Jaffey, supra note 229, at 34. The main body of contract
law generally is considered nonmandatory. See also Philip, supra note 224, at
83; Restatement (Second) Conflict of Laws 187 cmt. c (1971) ("Most rules
of contract law are designed to fill gaps in a contract which the parties could
themselves have filled with express provisions.").
n236. See Jackson, supra note 208, at 61; Philip, supra note 224,
at 84.
n237. See Philip, supra note 224, at 92-93; Wolfgang von
Bieberstein, Limitation of Party Autonomy in Private International Law by Rules
of Jus Cogens in Laws Protecting Agents and Distributors, in International
Contracts 93, 96 (Hans Smit et al. eds., 1981) ("The term ius cogens, or
mandatory provisions, [describes] rules which are binding on the parties and
cannot be avoided by contractual agreement in a domestic relationship.... The
question... [is] whether or not such rules are also regarded as having a
mandatory character [in] an international relationship...."). This same
principle holds true for cross-border (interstate) transactions within the
United States. See, e.g., Woods-Tucker Leasing Corp. v. Hutcheson-Ingram Dev.
Co., 642 F.2d 744, 750 (5th Cir. 1981) (displacing forum's usury restriction in
favor of contractually designated law of another state); Restatement (Second)
of Conflict of laws 187(2) (1971) (suggesting the possible displacement of law
that governs an issue the "parties could not have resolved by an explicit
provision in their agreement"); id. at 203 (suggesting conflicts analysis
for usury issues); Friedler, supra note 20, at 485 n.71 ("The validity of
contractual choice-of-law clauses as a matter of conflicts law relates to those
few issues that the parties are not free to resolve by an explicit provision in
their agreement, e.g., issues of capacity and essential validity.").
n238. See Weintraub, Functional Developments, supra note 20, at
258 ("The central transjurisdictional policy in contract-validity cases is
to encourage interstate and international commercial transactions. Enforcement
of local invalidating rules will discourage these transactions and be contrary
to the long-range best interests of even the state with the invalidating
rule.").
n239. I have suggested that likely externalities may be estimated
on the basis of either noncompliance with or repeal of the law in question
because noncompliance alone might not obviously reveal the "public"
nature of an obviously public law. An example might be the Copyright Act, 17
U.S.C. 101-20 (1994), whose public character some might argue is not
conclusively revealed through acts of infringement (which even en masse occur
principally in private relationships), but whose repeal clearly would expose
public injury resulting both from under- and over-protection of intellectual
property in the absence of the Act.
n240. See, e.g., the Sherman Act , 15 U.S.C. 1-7 (1994); the
Securities Acts, 15 U.S.C. 77-80; the Federal Bills of Lading Act, 49 U.S.C.
80101-80116 (1994); the Carriage of Goods by Sea Act (COGSA), 46 U.S.C.
1300-1315 (1994); the Copyright Act , 17 U.S.C. 101-20 (1994). Cataloging
public laws by applying the public/private and mandatory/nonmandatory dimensions
necessarily would be the subject of another article. Private litigants
contesting a law's categorization likely would expose relevant aspects of the
law in question that are simply beyond the scope of this Article. The examples
cited here are among the most obvious and are used for illustrative purposes
only. I have selected as examples laws that one is likely to encounter in
international commercial transactions having some nexus with the United States.
n241. U.C.C. art. 2 (1997).
n242. 15 U.S.C. 1-7.
n243. 15 U.S.C. 77-80.
n244. 46 U.S.C. 688 (1994).
n245. 49 U.S.C. 80101-80116.
n246. 46 U.S.C. 1300-1315.
n247. See supra note 187; see also, e.g., Trautman, supra note 4,
at 609 (concurring in the Second Circuit's assessment of the Jones Act as
"an ordinary rule of torts" (quoting Gerradin v. United Fruit Co., 60
F.2d 927, 929 (2nd Cir. 1932))); id. at 618 (describing the "primary
purpose" of the Jones Act as " extending or clarifying private
rights").
n248. See 46 U.S.C. 1303 for duties imposed by COGSA and 49 U.S.C.
80103-80114 for duties imposed by the Federal Bills of Lading Act.
n249. See 46 U.S.C. 1303-1304.
n250. Because the private law/public law dimension attempts to
categorize laws rather than transactions, other characteristics of a law in
addition to its "probable externalities" score might help determine
its classification as public or private. The availability of damages unrelated
to or in addition to actual loss (as in the Sherman Act and COGSA), the
imposition of minimum standards of conduct or safety (as in COGSA, the Federal
Bills of Lading Act, and the Securities and Exchange Act), or the possibility
of criminal in addition to civil liability as a result of noncompliance (as in
the Federal Bills of Lading Act and the Sherman Act) indicates a public law
classification. On the other hand, the closer the codified law to the subject
matter of traditional common law categories of private law - contracts, torts,
property, family law - the more likely the law's classification as private.
n251. See, e.g., Minnesota Mining and Mfg. Co. v. Graham-Field,
Inc., 96-3839, 1997 U.S. Dist. LEXIS 4457, at *7-9 (S.D.N.Y. Apr. 8, 1997);
supra note 233 and accompanying text.
n252. See supra note 198.
n253. See discussion supra Parts III.C and V.B.
n254. For this provision in COGSA, see 46 U.S.C. 1303(8) (1994).
For the Federal Bills of Lading Act, see 49 U.S.C. 80113(a) (1994).
n255. Precisely because one ordinarily would expect a law that
restricts private discretion in a way designed to serve the public interest not
to be prospectively waivable, the category of "nonmandatory public
laws" is probably not large. Examples might be laws that forbid certain
acts in the absence of consent or authorization by the affected party, such as
section 1101 of the Copyright Act, which forbids the unauthorized fixation and
trafficking in sound recordings and music videos, and subjects offenders to
remedies "to the same extent as an infringer of copyright." 17 U.S.C.
1101 (1994). Section 1101 might be an example of a prospectively waivable
public law that is displaceable by contractual election in appropriate
circumstances but not otherwise subject to choice of law analysis.
n256. See supra note 26 and accompanying text.
n257. See supra notes 30-36 and accompanying text. One commentator
has noted that:
Ordre public international serves as the "safety valve' of
private international law by barring the domestic application of an otherwise
competent rule of foreign law to the extent that it conflicts with the public
policy of the forum. It has no application to domestic law, which by definition
does not contradict domestic public policy.
Baade, supra note 15, at 453.
The fact that the "public policy exception" operates
most typically in favor of the forum's mandatory private law is reflected in
many cases. See To-Am Equip. Co. v. Mitsubishi Caterpillar Forklift Am., 913 F.
Supp. 1148, 1151 n.4 (N.D. Ill. 1995) (finding that the Illinois Franchise
Disclosure Act's anti-war provision trumped a contrary choice of law clause);
Solman Distribs. v. Brown-Forman Corp., 888 F.2d 170, 172 (1st Cir. 1989)
(deciding that a Maine statute regarding wholesale licensees trumped a contrary
conflicts rule); North Am. Bank, Ltd. v. Schulman, 474 N.Y.S.2d 383, 388
(N.Y.Co.Ct. 1984) (stating that New York's usury statute reflected public
policy barring application of a Israeli law that permitted a higher rate);
Blalock v. Perfect Subscription Co., 458 F. Supp. 123, 127 (S.D. Ala. 1978)
(deciding that an Alabama prohibition on covenants not to compete trumped the
contrary conflicts rule).
n258. The public policy exception traditionally has no application
to forum public law. Public policy properly is invoked as a reason for
declining to apply foreign law; it traditionally is not available as an excuse
for the selective application (i.e., occasional displacement) of the forum's
public law. As Professor Baade notes, public policy "has no application to
domestic law, which by definition does not contradict domestic public policy."
See supra text accompanying note 39.
n259. On the surface, the process and result of classifying laws
is reminiscent of the thirteenth and fourteenth century Italian statutists, who
determined a law's sphere of application according to the category in which it
was classified - a system whose eventual complications led to its demise. See,
e.g., Hessel E. Yntema, The Historical Bases of Private International Law, 2
Am. J. Comp. L. 297, 303-04 (1953); Maier, Extraterritorial Jurisdiction, supra
note 4, at 282 n.5; Paul, supra note 28, at 13-14. The classification that
occurs in the context of the public law taboo does not suffer a similar
infirmity. The sphere of application of a law within the taboo depends on the
law's intent, not on its categorization.
n260. Clearly, public laws may designate their own scope of
application, and it seems something of an abdication of responsibility for
Congress, the Executive branch, or independent agencies responsible for public
law enforcement not to be more diligent with respect to issues of so-called
"extraterritorial" regulation. See supra notes 61, 204 and
accompanying text; see also, e.g., Commodities Exchange Act, 7 U.S.C. 2 (1994)
(disclaiming explicitly regulation of transactions in foreign currencies that
do not occur on a domestic board of trade); Salomon Forex, Inc. v. Tauber, 8
F.3d 966, 975-78 (4th Cir. 1993) (applying 7 U.S.C. 2).